请输入您要查询的百科知识:

 

词条 Axiom of regularity
释义

  1. Elementary implications of regularity

     No set is an element of itself  No infinite descending sequence of sets exists  Simpler set-theoretic definition of the ordered pair   Every set has an ordinal rank    For every two sets, only one can be an element of the other  

  2. The axiom of dependent choice and no infinite descending sequence of sets implies regularity

  3. Regularity and the rest of ZF(C) axioms

  4. Regularity and Russell's paradox

  5. Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types

  6. History

  7. Regularity in the presence of urelements

  8. See also

  9. References

  10. External links

In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every non-empty set A contains an element that is disjoint from A. In first-order logic, the axiom reads:

.

The axiom implies that no set is an element of itself, and that there is no infinite sequence (an) such that ai+1 is an element of ai for all i. With the axiom of dependent choice (which is a weakened form of the axiom of choice), this result can be reversed: if there are no such infinite sequences, then the axiom of regularity is true. Hence, the axiom of regularity is equivalent, given the axiom of dependent choice, to the alternative axiom that there are no downward infinite membership chains.

The axiom of regularity was introduced by {{harvtxt|von Neumann|1925}}; it was adopted in a formulation closer to the one found in contemporary textbooks by {{harvtxt|Zermelo|1930}}. Virtually all results in the branches of mathematics based on set theory hold even in the absence of regularity; see chapter 3 of {{harvtxt|Kunen|1980}}. However, regularity makes some properties of ordinals easier to prove; and it not only allows induction to be done on well-ordered sets but also on proper classes that are well-founded relational structures such as the lexicographical ordering on

Given the other axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the axiom of regularity is equivalent to the axiom of induction. The axiom of induction tends to be used in place of the axiom of regularity in intuitionistic theories (ones that do not accept the law of the excluded middle), where the two axioms are not equivalent.

In addition to omitting the axiom of regularity, non-standard set theories have indeed postulated the existence of sets that are elements of themselves.

Elementary implications of regularity

No set is an element of itself

Let A be a set, and apply the axiom of regularity to {A}, which is a set by the axiom of pairing. We see that there must be an element of {A} which is disjoint from {A}. Since the only element of {A} is A, it must be that A is disjoint from {A}. So, since A ∈ {A}, we cannot have AA (by the definition of disjoint).

No infinite descending sequence of sets exists

Suppose, to the contrary, that there is a function, f, on the natural numbers with f(n+1) an element of f(n) for each n. Define S = {f(n): n a natural number}, the range of f, which can be seen to be a set from the axiom schema of replacement. Applying the axiom of regularity to S, let B be an element of S which is disjoint from S. By the definition of S, B must be f(k) for some natural number k. However, we are given that f(k) contains f(k+1) which is also an element of S. So f(k+1) is in the intersection of f(k) and S. This contradicts the fact that they are disjoint sets. Since our supposition led to a contradiction, there must not be any such function, f.

The nonexistence of a set containing itself can be seen as a special case where the sequence is infinite and constant.

Notice that this argument only applies to functions f that can be represented as sets as opposed to undefinable classes. The hereditarily finite sets, Vω, satisfy the axiom of regularity (and all other axioms of ZFC except the axiom of infinity). So if one forms a non-trivial ultrapower of Vω, then it will also satisfy the axiom of regularity. The resulting model will contain elements, called non-standard natural numbers, that satisfy the definition of natural numbers in that model but are not really natural numbers. They are fake natural numbers which are "larger" than any actual natural number. This model will contain infinite descending sequences of elements. For example, suppose n is a non-standard natural number, then and , and so on. For any actual natural number k, . This is an unending descending sequence of elements. But this sequence is not definable in the model and thus not a set. So no contradiction to regularity can be proved.

Simpler set-theoretic definition of the ordered pair

The axiom of regularity enables defining the ordered pair (a,b) as {a,{a,b}}. See ordered pair for specifics. This definition eliminates one pair of braces from the canonical Kuratowski definition (a,b) = {{a},{a,b}}.

Every set has an ordinal rank

This was actually the original form of the axiom in von Neumann's axiomatization.

Suppose x is any set. Let t be the transitive closure of {x}. Let u be the subset of t consisting of unranked sets. If u is empty, then x is ranked and we are done. Otherwise, apply the axiom of regularity to u to get an element w of u which is disjoint from u. Since w is in u, w is unranked. w is a subset of t by the definition of transitive closure. Since w is disjoint from u, every element of w is ranked. Applying the axioms of replacement and union to combine the ranks of the elements of w, we get an ordinal rank for w, to wit . This contradicts the conclusion that w is unranked. So the assumption that u was non-empty must be false and x must have rank.

For every two sets, only one can be an element of the other

Let X and Y be sets. Then apply the axiom of regularity to the set {X,Y}. We see there must be an element of {X,Y} which is also disjoint from it. It must be either X or Y. By the definition of disjoint then, we must have either Y is not an element of X or vice versa.

The axiom of dependent choice and no infinite descending sequence of sets implies regularity

Let the non-empty set S be a counter-example to the axiom of regularity; that is, every element of S has a non-empty intersection with S. We define a binary relation R on S by , which is entire by assumption. Thus, by the axiom of dependent choice, there is some sequence (an) in S satisfying anRan+1 for all n in N. As this is an infinite descending chain, we arrive at a contradiction and so, no such S exists.

Regularity and the rest of ZF(C) axioms

Regularity was shown to be relatively consistent with the rest of ZF by {{harvtxt|Skolem|1923}} and {{harvtxt|von Neumann|1929}}, meaning that if ZF without regularity is consistent, then ZF (with regularity) is also consistent. For his proof in modern notation see {{harvtxt|Vaught|2001|loc=§10.1}} for instance.

The axiom of regularity was also shown to be independent from the other axioms of ZF(C), assuming they are consistent. The result was announced by Paul Bernays in 1941, although he did not publish a proof until 1954. The proof involves (and led to the study of) Rieger-Bernays permutation models (or method), which were used for other proofs of independence for non-well-founded systems ({{harvnb|Rathjen|2004|p=193}} and {{harvnb|Forster|2003|pp=210–212}}).

Regularity and Russell's paradox

Naive set theory (the axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension and the axiom of extensionality) is inconsistent due to Russell's paradox. In early formalizations of sets, mathematicians and logicians have avoided that contradiction by replacing the axiom schema of comprehension with the much weaker axiom schema of separation. However, this step alone takes one to theories of sets which are considered too weak. So some of the power of comprehension was added back via the other existence axioms of ZF set theory (pairing, union, powerset, replacement, and infinity) which may be regarded as special cases of comprehension. So far, these axioms do not seem to lead to any contradiction. Subsequently, the axiom of choice and the axiom of regularity were added to exclude models with some undesirable properties. These two axioms are known to be relatively consistent.

In the presence of the axiom schema of separation, Russell's paradox becomes a proof that there is no set of all sets. The axiom of regularity together with the axiom of pairing also prohibit such a universal set. However, Russell's paradox yields a proof that there is no "set of all sets" using the axiom schema of separation alone, without any additional axioms. In particular, ZF without the axiom of regularity already prohibits such a universal set.

If a theory is extended by adding an axiom or axioms, then any (possibly undesirable) consequences of the original theory remain consequences of the extended theory. In particular, if ZF without regularity is extended by adding regularity to get ZF, then any contradiction (such as Russell's paradox) which followed from the original theory would still follow in the extended theory.

The existence of Quine atoms (sets that satisfy the formula equation x = {x}, i.e. have themselves as their only elements) is consistent with the theory obtained by removing the axiom of regularity from ZFC. Various non-wellfounded set theories allow "safe" circular sets, such as Quine atoms, without becoming inconsistent by means of Russell's paradox.{{harv|Rieger|2011|pp=175,178}}

Regularity, the cumulative hierarchy, and types

In ZF it can be proven that the class , called the von Neumann universe, is equal to the class of all sets. This statement is even equivalent to the axiom of regularity (if we work in ZF with this axiom omitted). From any model which does not satisfy axiom of regularity, a model which satisfies it can be constructed by taking only sets in .

{{harvs|txt|last=Enderton|first=Herbert|year=1977|loc=p. 206|author-link=Herbert Enderton}} wrote that "The idea of rank is a descendant of Russell's concept of type". Comparing ZF with type theory, Alasdair Urquhart wrote that "Zermelo's system has the notational advantage of not containing any explicitly typed variables, although in fact it can be seen as having an implicit type structure built into it, at least if the axiom of regularity is included. The details of this implicit typing are spelled out in Zermelo|1930}}|[Zermelo 1930], and again in a well-known article of George Boolos Boolos|1971}}|[Boolos 1971]." {{harvtxt|Urquhart|2003|p=305}}{{harvs|txt|last=Scott|first=Dana|year=1974|authorlink=Dana Scott}} went further and claimed that:{{quote|The truth is that there is only one satisfactory way of avoiding the paradoxes: namely, the use of some form of the theory of types. That was at the basis of both Russell's and Zermelo's intuitions. Indeed the best way to regard Zermelo's theory is as a simplification and extension of Russell's. (We mean Russell's simple theory of types, of course.) The simplification was to make the types cumulative. Thus mixing of types is easier and annoying repetitions are avoided. Once the later types are allowed to accumulate the earlier ones, we can then easily imagine extending the types into the transfinite—just how far we want to go must necessarily be left open. Now Russell made his types explicit in his notation and Zermelo left them implicit. [emphasis in original]}}

In the same paper, Scott shows that an axiomatic system based on the inherent properties of the cumulative hierarchy turns out to be equivalent to ZF, including regularity.{{harv|Lévy|2002|p=73}}

History

The concept of well-foundedness and rank of a set were both introduced by Dmitry Mirimanoff (Mirimanoff|1917}}|1917) cf. {{harvtxt|Lévy|2002|p=68}} and {{harvtxt|Hallett|1986|loc=§4.4, esp. p. 186, 188}}. Mirimanoff called a set x "regular" (French: "ordinaire") if every descending chain xx1x2 ∋ ... is finite. Mirimanoff however did not consider his notion of regularity (and well-foundedness) as an axiom to be observed by all sets {{harv|Halbeisen|2012|pp=62–63}}; in later papers Mirimanoff also explored what are now called non-well-founded sets ("extraordinaire" in Mirimanoff's terminology) {{harv|Sangiorgi|2011|pp=17–19, 26}}.

{{harvtxt|Skolem|1923}} and {{harvtxt|von Neumann|1925}} pointed out that non-well-founded sets are superfluous (on p. 404 in van Heijenoort|1967}}|van Heijenoort's translation) and in the same publication von Neumann gives an axiom (p. 412 in translation) which excludes some, but not all, non-well-founded sets {{harv|Rieger|2011|p=179}}. In a subsequent publication, {{harvtxt|von Neumann|1928}} gave the following axiom (rendered in modern notation by A. Rieger):

.

Regularity in the presence of urelements

Urelements are objects that are not sets, but which can be elements of sets. In ZF set theory, there are no urelements, but in some other set theories such as ZFA, there are. In these theories, the axiom of regularity must be modified. The statement "" needs to be replaced with a statement that is not empty and is not an urelement. One suitable replacement is , which states that x is inhabited.

See also

  • Non-well-founded set theory
  • Scott's trick

References

  • {{citation |first=Paul Isaac|last= Bernays|authorlink=Paul Bernays| title= A system of axiomatic set theory. Part II |journal= The Journal of Symbolic Logic| volume= 6 |issue= 1| year = 1941 | pages = 1–17 | doi=10.2307/2267281 | jstor=2267281}}
  • {{citation | first= Paul Isaac|last = Bernays|authorlink=Paul Bernays| title= A system of axiomatic set theory. Part VII |journal = The Journal of Symbolic Logic| volume = 19 |issue = 2| year = 1954 | pages = 81–96 | doi=10.2307/2268864 | jstor=2268864}}
  • {{citation|last=Boolos|first= George |authorlink=George Boolos | year= 1971 | title = The iterative conception of set | journal = Journal of Philosophy | volume = 68 |issue= 8 |pages= 215–231 | doi=10.2307/2025204 | jstor=2025204}} reprinted in {{citation|last=Boolos|first= George |year=1998|title=Logic, Logic and Logic|pages=13–29|publisher=Harvard University Press}}
  • {{citation | last= Enderton | first = Herbert B. | title = Elements of Set Theory | publisher = Academic Press | year=1977}}
  • {{citation|title = Logic, induction and sets| last = Forster | first = T. | publisher = Cambridge University Press | year = 2003}}
  • {{citation| first= Lorenz J. |last = Halbeisen | title=Combinatorial Set Theory: With a Gentle Introduction to Forcing|year=2012|publisher=Springer}}
  • {{citation|first=Michael|last=Hallett|title=Cantorian set theory and limitation of size|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=1996|origyear=first published 1984|isbn=978-0-19-853283-5}}
  • {{Citation | last=Jech | first= Thomas |authorlink=Thomas Jech | year= 2003 |title = Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded |publisher=Springer| isbn = 978-3-540-44085-7}}
  • {{Citation | last=Kunen | first=Kenneth |authorlink=Kenneth Kunen | year = 1980|title = Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs| publisher=Elsevier| isbn=978-0-444-86839-8}}
  • {{cite book| last = Lévy | first =Azriel | authorlink=Azriel Lévy | isbn = 978-0-486-42079-0 | year =2002 |origyear= first published in 1979 | title=Basic set theory| publisher=Dover Publications|location=Mineola, New York}}
  • {{Citation | last1=Mirimanoff | first1=D. | title=Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali-Forti et le probleme fondamental de la theorie des ensembles | year=1917 | journal=L'Enseignement Mathématique | volume=19|pages=37–52}}
  • {{citation|editor1-first=Godehard |editor1-last=Link|title=One Hundred Years of Russell ́s Paradox: Mathematics, Logic, Philosophy|year=2004|publisher=Walter de Gruyter|isbn=978-3-11-019968-0| chapter =Predicativity, Circularity, and Anti-Foundation | first = M. | last= Rathjen| chapter-url=http://www1.maths.leeds.ac.uk/~rathjen/russelle.pdf}}
  • {{Citation

| last1 = Rieger | first1 = Adam
| chapter = Paradox, ZF, and the Axiom of Foundation
| doi = 10.1007/978-94-007-0214-1_9
| title = Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms. Essays in Honour of John L. Bell.
| editors = David DeVidi, Michael Hallett, Peter Clark
| series = The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science
| volume = 75
| pages = 171–187
| year = 2011
| isbn = 978-94-007-0213-4
| pmid =
| pmc =
| chapter-url = http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/3810/1/JLB.pdf| citeseerx = 10.1.1.100.9052
}}
  • {{citation | first = L. |last = Riegger | url = http://dml.cz/bitstream/handle/10338.dmlcz/100254/CzechMathJ_07-1957-3_1.pdf | title = A contribution to Gödel's axiomatic set theory | journal = Czechoslovak Mathematical Journal | volume = 7 | year = 1957 | pages = 323–357}}
  • {{citation| first = Davide | last = Sangiorgi | year = 2011 | chapter = Origins of bisimulation and coinduction | editor1-first = Davide | editor1-last = Sangiorgi | editor2-first = Jan | editor2-last = Rutten | title = Advanced Topics in Bisimulation and Coinduction | publisher = Cambridge University Press}}
  • {{citation | last = Scott | first = Dana Stewart | authorlink=Dana Scott | year = 1974 | chapter = Axiomatizing set theory | title = Axiomatic set theory. Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics Volume 13, Part II | pages = 207–214}}
  • {{cite book|ref=harv| last=Skolem| first=Thoralf|authorlink=Thoralf Skolem | year=1923|title=Axiomatized set theory}} Reprinted in From Frege to Gödel, van Heijenoort, 1967, in English translation by Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg, pp. 291–301.
  • {{citation|last = Urquhart|first = Alasdair | chapter = The Theory of Types | editor-last = Griffin| editor-first =Nicholas | title =The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell | publisher = Cambridge University Press | year=2003}}
  • {{citation|first=Robert L. |last = Vaught|title=Set Theory: An Introduction| year=2001| publisher=Springer| isbn=978-0-8176-4256-3| edition=2nd}}
  • {{citation|last=von Neumann|first = John| authorlink=John von Neumann|year=1925|title=Eine axiomatiserung der Mengenlehre|journal=Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik|volume=154|pages=219–240}}; translation in {{citation|last=van Heijenoort | first =Jean | year =1967 | title = From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931 | pages = 393–413 }}
  • {{citation|last = von Neumann|first = John| authorlink=John von Neumann |year= 1928|title= Über die Definition durch transfinite Induktion und verwandte Fragen der allgemeinen Mengenlehre| journal= Mathematische Annalen|volume = 99 |pages=373–391|doi=10.1007/BF01459102}}
  • {{citation| last = von Neumann |first = John| authorlink=John von Neumann| year = 1929 | title= Uber eine Widerspruchfreiheitsfrage in der axiomatischen Mengenlehre| journal = Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik |volume = 160 |issue = 160|pages = 227–241 | doi=10.1515/crll.1929.160.227}}
  • {{citation |last=Zermelo|first= Ernst |authorlink=Ernst Zermelo | year= 1930 | title = Über Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche. Neue Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre. | journal = Fundamenta Mathematicae | volume = 16 |pages= 29–47|url=http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm16/fm1615.pdf|doi= 10.4064/fm-16-1-29-47 }}; translation in {{citation | editor-last= Ewald |editor-first= W.B. | year = 1996| title = From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics Vol. 2 | publisher= Clarendon Press |pages = 1219–33}}

External links

  • {{PlanetMath|urlname=axiomoffoundation|title=Axiom of foundation}}
  • [https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/inhabited+set Inhabited set] and [https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/axiom+of+foundation the axiom of foundation] on nLab
{{Set theory}}{{DEFAULTSORT:Axiom Of Regularity}}

2 : Axioms of set theory|Wellfoundedness

随便看

 

开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。

 

Copyright © 2023 OENC.NET All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/11/14 18:48:52