词条 | Boltzmann brain |
释义 |
In physics thought experiments, a Boltzmann brain is a self-aware entity that arises due to extremely rare random fluctuations out of a state of thermodynamic equilibrium. For example, in a homogeneous Newtonian soup, theoretically by sheer chance all the atoms could bounce off and stick to one another in such a way as to assemble a functioning human brain (though this would, on average, take vastly longer than the current lifetime of the universe). The idea is indirectly named after the Austrian physicist Ludwig Boltzmann (1844–1906), who in 1896 published a theory that the Universe is observed to be in a highly improbable non-equilibrium state because only when such states randomly occur can brains exist to be aware of the Universe. One criticism of Boltzmann's "Boltzmann universe" hypothesis is that the most common thermal fluctuations are as close to equilibrium overall as possible; thus, by any reasonable criterion, human brains in a Boltzmann universe with myriad neighboring stars would be vastly outnumbered by "Boltzmann brains" existing alone in an empty universe. Boltzmann brains gained new relevance around 2002, when some cosmologists started to become concerned that, in many existing theories about the Universe, human brains in the current Universe appear to be vastly outnumbered by Boltzmann brains in the future Universe who, by chance, have exactly the same perceptions that we do; this leads to the absurd conclusion that statistically we ourselves are likely to be Boltzmann brains. Such a reductio ad absurdum argument is sometimes used to argue against certain theories of the Universe. When applied to more recent theories about the multiverse, Boltzmann brain arguments are part of the unsolved measure problem of cosmology. Boltzmann universeIn 1896, mathematician Ernst Zermelo advanced a theory that the Second Law of Thermodynamics was absolute rather than statistical.[1] Zermelo bolstered his theory by pointing out that the Poincaré recurrence theorem shows statistical entropy in a closed system must eventually be a periodic function; therefore, the Second Law, which is always observed to increase entropy, is unlikely to be statistical. To counter Zermelo's argument, Austrian physicist Ludwig Boltzmann advanced two theories. The first theory, now believed to be the correct one, is that the Universe started for some unknown reason in a low-entropy state. The second and alternative theory, published in 1896 but attributed in 1895 to Boltzmann's assistant Ignaz Schütz, is the "Boltzmann universe" scenario. In this scenario, the Universe spends the vast majority of eternity in a featureless state of heat death; however, over enough eons, eventually a very rare thermal fluctuation will occur where atoms bounce off each other in exactly such a way that it creates substructures such as our entire observable universe. Boltzmann argues that, while most of the Universe is featureless, we do not see those regions because they are devoid of intelligent life; to Boltzmann, it is unremarkable that we view solely the interior of our Boltzmann universe, as that is the only place where intelligent life lives. (This may be the first use in modern science of the anthropic principle).[2][3] In 1931, astronomer Arthur Eddington pointed out that, because a large fluctuation is exponentially less probable than a small fluctuation, observers in Boltzmann universes will be vastly outnumbered by observers in smaller fluctuations. Physicist Richard Feynman published a similar counterargument within his widely-read 1964 Feynman Lectures on Physics. By 2004 physicists had pushed Eddington's observation to its logical conclusion: the most numerous observers in an eternity of thermal fluctuations would be minimal "Boltzmann brains" popping up in an otherwise featureless universe.[2][4] CreationGiven enough time, every possible structure is formed via random fluctuation. Boltzmann-style thought experiments focus on structures like human brains that are presumably self-aware observers. Given any arbitrary criteria for what constitutes a Boltzmann brain (or planet, or universe), smaller structures that minimally and barely meet the criteria are vastly and exponentially more common than larger structures; a rough analogy is how the odds of a real English word showing up when you shake a box of Scrabble letters are greater than the odds that a whole English sentence or paragraph will form.[6] The average timescale required for formation of a Boltzmann brain is vastly greater than the current age of the Universe. In modern physics, Boltzmann brains can be formed either by quantum fluctuation, or by a thermal fluctuation generally involving nucleation.[2] Via quantum fluctuationBy one calculation, a Boltzmann brain appears as a quantum fluctuation in the vacuum after a time interval of years. This fluctuation can occur even in a true Minkowski vacuum (a flat spacetime vacuum lacking vacuum energy). Quantum mechanics heavily favors smaller fluctuations that "borrow" the least amount of energy from the vacuum. Typically, a quantum Boltzmann brain will suddenly appear from the vacuum (alongside an equivalent amount of virtual antimatter), remain only long enough to have a single coherent thought or observation, and then disappear into the vacuum as suddenly as it appeared. Such a brain is completely self-contained, and can never radiate energy out to infinity.[5] Via nucleationCurrent evidence suggests that the observable Universe is not a Minkowski space, but rather a de Sitter universe with a positive cosmological constant. In a de Sitter vacuum (but not in a Minkowski vacuum), a Boltzmann brain can form via nucleation of non-virtual particles gradually assembled by chance from the Hawking radiation emitted from the de Sitter space's bounded cosmological horizon. One estimate for the average time required until nucleation is around years.[5] A typical nucleated Boltzmann brain will, after it finishes its activity, cool off to absolute zero and eventually completely decay, as any isolated object would in the vacuum of space. Unlike the quantum fluctuation case, the Boltzmann brain will radiate energy out to infinity. In nucleation, the most common fluctuations are as close to thermal equilibrium overall as possible given whatever arbitrary criteria are provided for labeling a fluctuation a "Boltzmann brain".[2] Theoretically a Boltzmann brain can also form, albeit again with a tiny probability, at any time during the matter-dominated early universe.[6] Modern Boltzmann brain problemsMany cosmologists believe that if a theory predicts that Boltzmann brains with human-like experiences vastly outnumber normal human brains, then that theory should be rejected or disfavored. Others argue that brains produced via quantum fluctuation, and maybe even brains produced via nucleation in the de Sitter vacuum, don't count as observers. Quantum fluctuations are easier to exclude than nucleated brains, as quantum fluctuations can more easily be targeted by straightforward criteria (such as their lack of interaction with the environment at infinity).[2][5] Some cosmologists believe that a better understanding of the degrees of freedom in the quantum vacuum of holographic string theory can solve the Boltzmann brain problem.[7] In single-Universe scenariosIn a single de Sitter Universe with a cosmological constant, and starting from any finite spatial slice, the number of "normal" observers is finite and bounded by the heat death of the Universe. If the Universe lasts forever, the number of nucleated Boltzmann brains is, in most models, infinite; cosmologists such as Alan Guth worry that this would make it seem "infinitely unlikely for us to be normal brains".[8] One caveat is that if the Universe is a false vacuum that locally decays into a Minkowski or a big crunch-bound anti-de Sitter space in less than 20 billion years, then infinite Boltzmann nucleation is avoided. (If the average local false vacuum decay rate is over 20 billion years, Boltzmann brain nucleation is still infinite, as the Universe increases in size faster than local vacuum collapses destroy the portions of the Universe within the collapses' future light cones). Proposed hypothetical mechanisms to destroy the universe within that timeframe range from superheavy gravitinos to a heavier-than-observed top quark triggering "death by Higgs".[9][10][11] If no cosmological constant exists, and if the presently observed vacuum energy is from quintessence that will eventually completely dissipate, then infinite Boltzmann nucleation is also avoided.[12] In eternal inflation{{Further|Measure problem (cosmology)}}One class of solutions to the Boltzmann brain problem makes use of differing approaches to the measure problem in cosmology: in infinite multiverse theories, the ratio of normal observers to Boltzmann brains depends on how infinite limits are taken. Measures might be chosen to avoid appreciable fractions of Boltzmann brains.[13][14][15] Unlike the single-universe case, one challenge in finding a global solution in eternal inflation is that all possible string landscapes must be summed over; in some measures, having even a small fraction of universes infested with Boltzmann brains causes the measure of the multiverse as a whole to be dominated by Boltzmann brains.[11][16] The measurement problem in cosmology also grapples with the ratio of normal observers to abnormally early observers. In measures such as the proper time measure that suffer from an extreme "youngness" problem, the typical observer is a "Boltzmann baby" formed by rare fluctuation in an extremely hot, early universe.[6] See also{{col-begin|3}}{{Col-break}}
Notes1. ^Brush, S. G., Nebulous Earth: A History of Modern Planetary Physics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), [https://books.google.cz/books?id=vTBZyesS08kC&pg=PA129#v=onepage&q&f=false p. 129]. 2. ^1 2 3 4 Carroll, S. M., [https://arxiv.org/abs/1702.00850 "Why Boltzmann brains are bad"] (Ithaca, New York: arXiv, 2017). 3. ^{{cite book|last1=Bostrom|first1=Nick|title=Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy|date=2002|publisher=Psychology Press|isbn=9780415938587|language=en|chapter=Introduction}} 4. ^{{cite journal |last=Albrecht |first=Andreas |authorlink=Andreas Albrecht (cosmologist) |last2=Sorbo |first2=Lorenzo |date=September 2004 |title=Can the universe afford inflation? |url=http://adsabs.harvard.edu/cgi-bin/bib_query?arXiv:hep-th/0405270 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=70 |issue=6 |pages=063528 |bibcode=2004PhRvD..70f3528A |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.70.063528 |accessdate=16 December 2014 |arxiv=hep-th/0405270}} 5. ^1 2 Davenport, M., & Olum, K. D. (2010). Are there Boltzmann brains in the vacuum. arXiv preprint arXiv:1008.0808. 6. ^1 Bousso, R., Freivogel, B., & Yang, I. S. (2008). Boltzmann babies in the proper time measure. Physical Review D, 77(10), 103514. 7. ^Garriga, J., & Vilenkin, A. (2009). Holographic multiverse. Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics, 2009(01), 021. 8. ^1 {{cite news|last1=Overbye|first1=Dennis|title=Big Brain Theory: Have Cosmologists Lost Theirs?|url=https://www.nytimes.com/2008/01/15/science/15brain.html?pagewanted=all|accessdate=26 February 2018|work=The New York Times|date=2008}} 9. ^{{cite news|title=Death by Higgs rids cosmos of space brain threat|url=https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21929333-200-death-by-higgs-rids-cosmos-of-space-brain-threat/|accessdate=26 February 2018|work=New Scientist|date=15 February 2017}} 10. ^Boddy, K. K., & Carroll, S. M. (2013). Can the Higgs Boson Save Us From the Menace of the Boltzmann Brains?. arXiv preprint arXiv:1308.4686. 11. ^1 Linde, A. (2007). Sinks in the landscape, Boltzmann brains and the cosmological constant problem. Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics, 2007(01), 022. 12. ^Carlip, S. (2007). Transient observers and variable constants or repelling the invasion of the Boltzmann’s brains. Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics, 2007(06), 001. 13. ^{{cite journal |author1=Andrea De Simone|author2=Alan H. Guth|author3=Andrei Linde|author4=Mahdiyar Noorbala|author5=Michael P. Salem|author6=Alexander Vilenkin|title=Boltzmann brains and the scale-factor cutoff measure of the multiverse|journal=Phys. Rev. D|date=14 Sep 2010|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.82.063520|arxiv= 0808.3778 |bibcode= 2010PhRvD..82f3520D|volume=82|issue=6|pages=063520}} 14. ^{{cite journal |author1=Andrei Linde|author2=Vitaly Vanchurin|author3=Sergei Winitzki|title=Stationary Measure in the Multiverse|journal=Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics|date=15 Jan 2009|issue=1|doi=10.1088/1475-7516/2009/01/031|arxiv= 0812.0005 |bibcode= 2009JCAP...01..031L|volume=2009|page=031}} 15. ^{{cite journal |author1=Andrei Linde|author2=Mahdiyar Noorbala|title=Measure problem for eternal and non-eternal inflation|journal=Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics|date=9 Sep 2010|issue=9|doi=10.1088/1475-7516/2010/09/008|arxiv= 1006.2170 |bibcode= 2010JCAP...09..008L|volume=2010|page=008}} 16. ^Bousso, R., & Freivogel, B. (2007). A paradox in the global description of the multiverse. Journal of High Energy Physics, 2007(06), 018. Further reading{{refbegin}}
4 : Paradoxes|Philosophy of thermal and statistical physics|Physical cosmology|Thought experiments in philosophy of mind |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。