词条 | Collatz conjecture | |||||||||||||||
释义 |
The Collatz conjecture is a conjecture in mathematics that concerns a sequence defined as follows: start with any positive integer n. Then each term is obtained from the previous term as follows: if the previous term is even, the next term is one half the previous term. If the previous term is odd, the next term is 3 times the previous term plus 1. The conjecture is that no matter what value of n, the sequence will always reach 1. The conjecture is named after Lothar Collatz, who introduced the idea in 1937, two years after receiving his doctorate.[1] It is also known as the 3n + 1 conjecture, the Ulam conjecture (after Stanisław Ulam), Kakutani's problem (after Shizuo Kakutani), the Thwaites conjecture (after Sir Bryan Thwaites), Hasse's algorithm (after Helmut Hasse), or the Syracuse problem;[2]{{refn|According to {{named ref|name=Lagarias (1985)}} p. 4, the name "Syracuse problem" was proposed by Hasse in the 1950s, during a visit to Syracuse University.}} the sequence of numbers involved is referred to as the hailstone sequence or hailstone numbers (because the values are usually subject to multiple descents and ascents like hailstones in a cloud),[3][4] or as wondrous numbers.[5] Paul Erdős said about the Collatz conjecture: "Mathematics may not be ready for such problems."[6] He also offered $500 for its solution.[6] Jeffrey Lagarias in 2010 claimed that based only on known information about this problem, "this is an extraordinarily difficult problem, completely out of reach of present day mathematics."[7]Statement of the problemConsider the following operation on an arbitrary positive integer:
In modular arithmetic notation, define the function f as follows: Now form a sequence by performing this operation repeatedly, beginning with any positive integer, and taking the result at each step as the input at the next. In notation: (that is: is the value of applied to recursively times; ). The Collatz conjecture is: This process will eventually reach the number 1, regardless of which positive integer is chosen initially. That smallest i such that ai = 1 is called the total stopping time of n. The conjecture asserts that every n has a well-defined total stopping time. If, for some n, such an i doesn't exist, we say that n has infinite total stopping time and the conjecture is false. If the conjecture is false, it can only be because there is some starting number which gives rise to a sequence that does not contain 1. Such a sequence might enter a repeating cycle that excludes 1, or increase without bound. No such sequence has been found. ExamplesFor instance, starting with n = 12, one gets the sequence 12, 6, 3, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1. n = 19, for example, takes longer to reach 1: 19, 58, 29, 88, 44, 22, 11, 34, 17, 52, 26, 13, 40, 20, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1. The sequence for n = 27, listed and graphed below, takes 111 steps (41 steps through odd numbers, in large font), climbing to a high of 9232 before descending to 1. 27, 82, 41, 124, 62, 31, 94, 47, 142, 71, 214, 107, 322, 161, 484, 242, 121, 364, 182, 91, 274, 137, 412, 206, 103, 310, 155, 466, 233, 700, 350, 175, 526, 263, 790, 395, 1186, 593, 1780, 890, 445, 1336, 668, 334, 167, 502, 251, 754, 377, 1132, 566, 283, 850, 425, 1276, 638, 319, 958, 479, 1438, 719, 2158, 1079, 3238, 1619, 4858, 2429, 7288, 3644, 1822, 911, 2734, 1367, 4102, 2051, 6154, 3077, 9232, 4616, 2308, 1154, 577, 1732, 866, 433, 1300, 650, 325, 976, 488, 244, 122, 61, 184, 92, 46, 23, 70, 35, 106, 53, 160, 80, 40, 20, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1 {{OEIS|id=A008884}} Numbers with a total stopping time longer than that of any smaller starting value form a sequence beginning with: 1, 2, 3, 6, 7, 9, 18, 25, 27, 54, 73, 97, 129, 171, 231, 313, 327, 649, 703, 871, 1161, 2223, 2463, 2919, 3711, 6171, … {{OEIS|A006877}}. The starting values whose maximum trajectory point is greater than that of any smaller starting value are as follows: 1, 2, 3, 7, 15, 27, 255, 447, 639, 703, 1819, 4255, 4591, 9663, 20895, 26623, 31911, 60975, 77671, 113383, 138367, 159487, 270271, 665215, 704511, ... {{OEIS|id=A006884}} Number of steps for n to reach 1 are 0, 1, 7, 2, 5, 8, 16, 3, 19, 6, 14, 9, 9, 17, 17, 4, 12, 20, 20, 7, 7, 15, 15, 10, 23, 10, 111, 18, 18, 18, 106, 5, 26, 13, 13, 21, 21, 21, 34, 8, 109, 8, 29, 16, 16, 16, 104, 11, 24, 24, ... {{OEIS|id=A006577}} The longest progression for any initial starting number less than 10 is 9, which has 19 steps, less than 100 is 97, which has 118 steps, less than 1,000 is 871, which has 178 steps, less than 10,000 is 6,171, which has 261 steps, less than 100,000 is 77,031, which has 350 steps, less than 1 million is 837,799, which has 524 steps, less than 10 million is 8,400,511, which has 685 steps, less than 100 million is 63,728,127, which has 949 steps, less than 1 billion is 670,617,279, which has 986 steps, less than 10 billion is 9,780,657,630, which has 1132 steps,[8] less than 100 billion is 75,128,138,247, which has 1228 steps, less than 1 trillion is 989,345,275,647, which has 1348 steps, less than 10 trillion is 7,887,663,552,367, which has 1563 steps, less than 100 trillion is 80,867,137,596,217, which has 1662 steps, less than 1 quadrillion is 942,488,749,153,153, which has 1862 steps, less than 10 quadrillion is 7,579,309,213,675,935, which has 1958 steps, and less than 100 quadrillion is 93,571,393,692,802,302, which has 2091 steps.[9] Note: these numbers are the lowest ones with the indicated step count, but not necessarily the only ones below the given limit. For instance, 9,780,657,631 has 1132 steps as well. The powers of two converge to one quickly because is halved times to reach one, and is never increased. VisualizationsCyclesAny counterexample to the Collatz conjecture would have to consist either of an infinite divergent trajectory or a cycle different from the trivial (4; 2; 1) cycle. Thus, if one could prove that neither of these types of counterexample could exist, then all positive integers would have a trajectory that reaches the trivial cycle. Such a strong result is not known, but certain types of cycles have been ruled out. The type of a cycle may be defined with reference to the "shortcut" definition of the Collatz map, for odd n and for even n. A cycle is a {{nowrap|sequence }} where , , and so on, up to in a closed loop. For this shortcut definition, the only known cycle is (1; 2). Although 4 is part of the single known cycle for the original Collatz map, it is not part of the cycle for the shortcut map. A k-cycle is a cycle that can be partitioned into 2k contiguous subsequences: k increasing sequences of odd numbers alternating with k decreasing sequences of even numbers. For instance, if the cycle consists of a single increasing sequence of odd numbers followed by a decreasing sequence of even numbers, it is called a 1-cycle.[12] Steiner (1977) proved that there is no 1-cycle other than the trivial (1;2).[13] Simons (2004) used Steiner's method to prove that there is no 2-cycle.[10] Simons & de Weger (2005) extended this proof up to 68-cycles: there is no k-cycle up to k = 68.[12] Beyond 68, this method gives upper bounds for the elements in such a cycle: for example, if there is a 75-cycle, then at least one element of the cycle is less than 2385×250.[12] Therefore, as exhaustive computer searches continue, larger cycles may be ruled out. To state the argument more intuitively: we need not look for cycles that have at most 68 trajectories, where each trajectory consists of consecutive ups followed by consecutive downs. See below for an idea of how one might find an upper bound for the elements of a cycle. Supporting argumentsAlthough the conjecture has not been proven, most mathematicians who have looked into the problem think the conjecture is true because experimental evidence and heuristic arguments support it. Experimental evidence{{asof|2017}}, the conjecture has been checked by computer for all starting values up to 87 * 260.[11] All initial values tested so far eventually end in the repeating cycle (4; 2; 1), which has only three terms. From this lower bound on the starting value, a lower bound can also be obtained for the number of terms a repeating cycle other than (4; 2; 1) must have.[12] When this relationship was established in 1981, the formula gave a lower bound of 35,400 terms.[12]This computer evidence is not a proof that the conjecture is true. As shown in the cases of the Pólya conjecture, the Mertens conjecture, and Skewes' number, sometimes a conjecture's only counterexamples are found when using very large numbers. A probabilistic heuristicIf one considers only the odd numbers in the sequence generated by the Collatz process, then each odd number is on average 3/4 of the previous one.{{refn|{{named ref|name=Lagarias (1985)}} section "A heuristic argument".}} (More precisely, the geometric mean of the ratios of outcomes is 3/4.) This yields a heuristic argument that every Hailstone sequence should decrease in the long run, although this is not evidence against other cycles, only against divergence. The argument is not a proof because it assumes that Hailstone sequences are assembled from uncorrelated probabilistic events. (It does rigorously establish that the 2-adic extension of the Collatz process has two division steps for every multiplication step for almost all 2-adic starting values.) And even if the probabilistic reasoning were rigorous, this would still imply only that the conjecture is almost surely true for any given integer, which does not necessarily imply that it is true for all integers. Rigorous boundsAlthough it is not known rigorously whether all positive numbers eventually reach one according to the Collatz iteration, it is known that many numbers do so. In particular, Krasikov and Lagarias showed that the number of integers in the interval [1,x] that eventually reach one is at least proportional to x0.84.[13] Other formulations of the conjectureIn reverseThere is another approach to prove the conjecture, which considers the bottom-up method of growing the so-called Collatz graph. The Collatz graph is a graph defined by the inverse relation So, instead of proving that all positive integers eventually lead to 1, we can try to prove that 1 leads to all positive integers. For any integer n, n ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff 3n + 1 ≡ 4 (mod 6). Equivalently, (n − 1)/3 ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff n ≡ 4 (mod 6). Conjecturally, this inverse relation forms a tree except for the 1–2–4 loop (the inverse of the 4–2–1 loop of the unaltered function f defined in the Statement of the problem section of this article). When the relation 3n + 1 of the function f is replaced by the common substitute "shortcut" relation (3n + 1)/2, the Collatz graph is defined by the inverse relation, For any integer n, n ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff (3n + 1)/2 ≡ 2 (mod 3). Equivalently, (2n − 1)/3 ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff n ≡ 2 (mod 3). Conjecturally, this inverse relation forms a tree except for a 1–2 loop (the inverse of the 1–2 loop of the function f(n) revised as indicated above). Alternately, replace the 3n + 1 with n' / H(n') where n' = 3n + 1 and H(n') is the highest power of 2 that divides n' (with no remainder). The resulting function f maps from odd numbers to odd numbers. Now suppose that for some odd number n, applying this operation k times yields the number 1 (that is, ). Then in binary, the number n can be written as the concatenation of strings wk wk−1 … w1 where each wh is a finite and contiguous extract from the representation of 1/3h.[14] The representation of n therefore holds the repetends of 1/3h, where each repetend is optionally rotated and then replicated up to a finite number of bits. It is only in binary that this occurs.[15] Conjecturally, every binary string s that ends with a '1' can be reached by a representation of this form (where we may add or delete leading '0's to s). As an abstract machine that computes in base twoRepeated applications of the Collatz function can be represented as an abstract machine that handles strings of bits. The machine will perform the following three steps on any odd number until only one "1" remains:
This prescription is plainly equivalent to computing a Hailstone sequence in base two. ExampleThe starting number 7 is written in base two as 111. The resulting Hailstone sequence is: 111110111100011110111011 As a parity sequenceFor this section, consider the Collatz function in the slightly modified form This can be done because when n is odd, 3n + 1 is always even. If P(…) is the parity of a number, that is P(2n) = 0 and P(2n + 1) = 1, then we can define the Hailstone parity sequence (or parity vector) for a number n as pi = P(ai), where a0 = n, and ai+1 = f(ai). What operation is performed (3n + 1)/2 or n/2 depends on the parity. The parity sequence is the same as the sequence of operations. Using this form for f(n), it can be shown that the parity sequences for two numbers m and n will agree in the first k terms if and only if m and n are equivalent modulo 2k. This implies that every number is uniquely identified by its parity sequence, and moreover that if there are multiple Hailstone cycles, then their corresponding parity cycles must be different.[16] Applying the f function k times to the number n=a·2k + b will give the result a·3c + d, where d is the result of applying the f function k times to b, and c is how many increases were encountered during that sequence (e.g. for a·25 + 1 there are 3 increases as 1 iterates to 2, 1, 2, 1, and finally to 2 so the result is a·33+2; for a·22 + 1 there is only 1 increase as 1 rises to 2 and falls to 1 so the result is a·3 + 1). When b is 2k - 1 then there will be k rises and the result will be 2·a·3k - 1. The factor of 3 multiplying a is independent of the value of a; it depends only on the behavior of b. This allows one to predict that certain forms of numbers will always lead to a smaller number after a certain number of iterations, e.g. 4a + 1 becomes 3a + 1 after two applications of f and 16a + 3 becomes 9·a + 2 after 4 applications of f. Whether those smaller numbers continue to 1, however, depends on the value of a. As a tag systemFor the Collatz function in the form Hailstone sequences can be computed by the extremely simple 2-tag system with production rules a → bc, b → a, c → aaa. In this system, the positive integer n is represented by a string of n a, and iteration of the tag operation halts on any word of length less than 2. (Adapted from De Mol.) The Collatz conjecture equivalently states that this tag system, with an arbitrary finite string of a's as the initial word, eventually halts (see Computation of Collatz sequences for a worked example). Extensions to larger domainsIterating on all integersAn extension to the Collatz conjecture is to include all integers, not just positive integers. Leaving aside the cycle 0 → 0 which cannot be entered from outside, there are a total of 4 known cycles, which all nonzero integers seem to eventually fall into under iteration of f. These cycles are listed here, starting with the well-known cycle for positive n: Odd values are listed in large bold. Each cycle is listed with its member of least absolute value (which is always odd) first.
The generalized Collatz conjecture is the assertion that every integer, under iteration by f, eventually falls into one of the four cycles above or the cycle 0 → 0. The 0 → 0 cycle is often regarded as "trivial" by the argument, as it is only included for the sake of completeness. Iterating with odd denominators or 2-adic integersThe standard Collatz map can be extended to (positive or negative) rational numbers which have odd denominators when written in lowest terms. The number is taken to be odd or even according to whether its numerator is odd or even. A closely related fact is that the Collatz map extends to the ring of 2-adic integers, which contains the ring of rationals with odd denominators as a subring. The parity sequences as defined above are no longer unique for fractions. However, it can be shown that any possible parity cycle is the parity sequence for exactly one fraction{{Citation needed|date=December 2018}}: if a cycle has length n and includes odd numbers exactly m times at indices k0, …, km−1, then the unique fraction which generates that parity cycle is {{NumBlk|::||{{EquationRef|1}}}}For example, the parity cycle (1 0 1 1 0 0 1) has length 7 and has 4 odd numbers at indices 0, 2, 3, and 6. The unique fraction which generates that parity cycle is the complete cycle being: 151/47 → 250/47 → 125/47 → 211/47 → 340/47 → 170/47 → 85/47 → 151/47 Although the cyclic permutations of the original parity sequence are unique fractions, the cycle is not unique, each permutation's fraction being the next number in the loop cycle: (0 1 1 0 0 1 1) → (1 1 0 0 1 1 0) → (1 0 0 1 1 0 1) → (0 0 1 1 0 1 1) → (0 1 1 0 1 1 0) → (1 1 0 1 1 0 0) → Also, for uniqueness, the parity sequence should be "prime", i.e., not partitionable into identical sub-sequences. For example, parity sequence (1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0) can be partitioned into two identical sub-sequences (1 1 0 0)(1 1 0 0). Calculating the 8-element sequence fraction gives (1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0) → But when reduced to lowest terms {5/7}, it is the same as that of the 4-element sub-sequence (1 1 0 0) → And this is because the 8-element parity sequence actually represents two circuits of the loop cycle defined by the 4-element parity sequence. In this context, the Collatz conjecture is equivalent to saying that (0 1) is the only cycle which is generated by positive whole numbers (i.e. 1 and 2). Cycle bounds{{EquationNote|1|Eq. (1)}} also gives a rough idea about how one can prove that cycles of certain lengths do not exist. For a hypothetical cycle of length n, the numerator is bounded above by 3n - 2n (this corresponds to a cycle of all odd numbers). A lower bound for the denominator can be obtained by letting n/m be an optimal rational approximation to log(3)/log(2). Together these give an upper bound for the unique fraction that generates a cycle of length n. If this upper bound is smaller than the largest number for which the conjecture has been verified to hold, then a cycle of length n is impossible.Iterating on real or complex numbersThe Collatz map can be viewed as the restriction to the integers of the smooth real and complex map which simplifies to If the standard Collatz map defined above is optimized by replacing the relation 3n + 1 with the common substitute "shortcut" relation (3n + 1)/2, it can be viewed as the restriction to the integers of the smooth real and complex map which simplifies to . Collatz fractalIterating the above optimized map in the complex plane produces the Collatz fractal. The point of view of iteration on the real line was investigated by {{named ref|name=Chamberland (1996)}} and on the complex plane by {{named ref|name=Letherman, Schleicher, and Wood (1999)|separator=.}} {{clear}}OptimizationsTime–space tradeoffThe section As a parity sequence above gives a way to speed up simulation of the sequence. To jump ahead k steps on each iteration (using the f function from that section), break up the current number into two parts, b (the k least significant bits, interpreted as an integer), and a (the rest of the bits as an integer). The result of jumping ahead k steps can be found as: f k(a 2k + b) = a 3c(b) + d(b). The c (or better 3c) and d arrays are precalculated for all possible k-bit numbers b, where d(b) is the result of applying the f function k times to b, and c(b) is the number of odd numbers encountered on the way.[17] For example, if k=5, you can jump ahead 5 steps on each iteration by separating out the 5 least significant bits of a number and using: c(0..31) = {0,3,2,2,2,2,2,4,1,4,1,3,2,2,3,4,1,2,3,3,1,1,3,3,2,3,2,4,3,3,4,5} d(0..31) = {0,2,1,1,2,2,2,20,1,26,1,10,4,4,13,40,2,5,17,17,2,2,20,20,8,22,8,71,26,26,80,242}. This requires 2k precomputation and storage to speed up the resulting calculation by a factor of k, a space–time tradeoff. Modular restrictionsFor the special purpose of searching for a counterexample to the Collatz conjecture, this precomputation leads to an even more important acceleration, used by Tomás Oliveira e Silva in his computational confirmations of the Collatz conjecture up to large values of n. If, for some given b and k, the inequality f k(a 2k + b) = a 3c(b) + d(b) < a 2k + b holds for all a, then the first counterexample, if it exists, cannot be b modulo 2k.[12] For instance, the first counterexample must be odd because f(2n) = n, smaller than 2n; and it must be 3 mod 4 because f2(4n + 1) = 3n + 1, smaller than 4n + 1. For each starting value a which is not a counterexample to the Collatz conjecture, there is a k for which such an inequality holds, so checking the Collatz conjecture for one starting value is as good as checking an entire congruence class. As k increases, the search only needs to check those residues b that are not eliminated by lower values of k. Only an exponentially small fraction of the residues survive.{{refn|{{named ref|name=Lagarias (1985)}} Theorem D.}} For example, the only surviving residues mod 32 are 7, 15, 27, and 31. Syracuse functionIf is an odd integer, then is even, so with odd and . The Syracuse function is the function from the set of odd integers into itself, for which {{OEIS|id=A075677}}. Some properties of the Syracuse function are:
The Collatz conjecture is equivalent to the statement that, for all in , there exists an integer such that . Undecidable generalizationsIn 1972, J. H. Conway proved that a natural generalization of the Collatz problem is algorithmically undecidable.[18] Specifically, he considered functions of the form where are rational numbers which are so chosen that is always integral. The standard Collatz function is given by , , , , . Conway proved that the problem: Given g and n, does the sequence of iterates reach 1? is undecidable, by representing the halting problem in this way. Closer to the Collatz problem is the following universally quantified problem: Given g does the sequence of iterates reach 1, for all {{tmath|n>0}}? Modifying the condition in this way can make a problem either harder or easier to solve (intuitively, it is harder to justify a positive answer but might be easier to justify a negative one). Kurtz and Simon[19] proved that the above problem is, in fact, undecidable and even higher in the arithmetical hierarchy, specifically -complete. This hardness result holds even if one restricts the class of functions g by fixing the modulus P to 6480.[20] See also{{portal|Mathematics|Number theory}}
Further reading
This volume,[21] edited by Jeffrey Lagarias and published by the American Mathematical Society, is a compendium of information on the Collatz conjecture, methods of approaching it and generalizations. It includes two survey papers by the editor and five by other authors, concerning the history of the problem, generalizations, statistical approaches and results from the theory of computation. It also includes reprints of early papers on the subject (including an entry by Lothar Collatz). References1. ^{{cite web|last1= O'Connor|first1=J.J.|last2=Robertson|first2=E.F.|title=Lothar Collatz|year=2006|url=http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Collatz.html|publisher=St Andrews University School of Mathematics and Statistics, Scotland}} [23][25][31][32]2. ^{{cite book |last1=Maddux |first1=Cleborne D. |last2=Johnson |first2=D. Lamont |year=1997 |title=Logo: A Retrospective |publisher=Haworth Press |location=New York |isbn=0-7890-0374-0 |page=160 |quote=The problem is also known by several other names, including: Ulam's conjecture, the Hailstone problem, the Syracuse problem, Kakutani's problem, Hasse's algorithm, and the Collatz problem.}} 3. ^{{cite book |last=Pickover |first=Clifford A. |year=2001 |title=Wonders of Numbers |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=0-19-513342-0 |pages=116–118}} 4. ^{{cite web |title=Hailstone Number |url=http://mathworld.wolfram.com/HailstoneNumber.html |work=MathWorld |publisher=Wolfram Research}} 5. ^{{cite book |last=Hofstadter |first=Douglas R. |authorlink=Douglas Hofstadter |year=1979 |title=Gödel, Escher, Bach |publisher=Basic Books |location=New York |isbn=0-465-02685-0 |pages=400–2}} 6. ^{{cite journal |last=Guy |first=R. K. |year=1983 |title=Don't try to solve these problems |journal=Amer. Math. Monthly |volume=90 |issue= |pages=35–41 |jstor=2975688 |doi=10.2307/2975688}} By this Erdos means that there aren't powerful tools for manipulating such objects. 7. ^{{cite book |editor1-last=Lagarias |editor1-first=Jeffrey C. |date=2010 |title=The ultimate challenge: the 3x+1 problem |publisher=American Mathematical Society |location=Providence, R.I. |isbn=0821849409 |page=4}} 8. ^{{cite journal |last1=Leavens |first1=Gary T. |last2=Vermeulen |first2=Mike |date=December 1992 |title=3x+1 Search Programs |journal=Computers & Mathematics with Applications |volume=24 |issue=11 |pages=79–99 |doi=10.1016/0898-1221(92)90034-F}} 9. ^{{cite web |last=Roosendaal |first=Eric |title=3x+1 Delay Records |url=http://www.ericr.nl/wondrous/delrecs.html |accessdate=30 June 2017}} (Note: "Delay records" are total stopping time records.) 10. ^{{cite journal |last=Simons |first=John L. |year=2005 |title=On the nonexistence of 2-cycles for the 3x+1 problem |journal=Math. Comp. |volume=74 |issue= |pages=1565–72 |mr=2137019 |url=http://www.ams.org/journals/mcom/2005-74-251/S0025-5718-04-01728-4/ |doi=10.1090/s0025-5718-04-01728-4}} 11. ^{{cite web |last=Roosendaal |first=Eric |title=On the 3x+1 Problem |url=http://www.ericr.nl/wondrous/ |accessdate=6 June 2018}} 12. ^1 2 {{cite web |last=Garner |first=Lynn E. |title=On The Collatz 3n + 1 Algorithm |url=http://www.ams.org/journals/proc/1981-082-01/S0002-9939-1981-0603593-2/S0002-9939-1981-0603593-2.pdf |format=PDF |accessdate=27 March 2015}} 13. ^{{Cite journal | last1 = Krasikov | first1 = Ilia | last2 = Lagarias | first2 = Jeffrey C. | authorlink2 = Jeffrey Lagarias | year = 2003 | title = Bounds for the 3x + 1 problem using difference inequalities | journal = Acta Arithmetica | doi = 10.4064/aa109-3-4 | mr = 1980260 | volume = 109 | issue = 3 | pages = 237–258| arxiv = math/0205002| bibcode = 2003AcAri.109..237K}} 14. ^{{cite journal |last=Colussi |first=Livio |date=9 September 2011 |title=The convergence classes of Collatz function |journal=Theoretical Computer Science |doi=10.1016/j.tcs.2011.05.056 |volume=412 |issue=39 |pages=5409–5419}} 15. ^{{cite journal |last=Hew |first=Patrick Chisan |date=7 March 2016 |title=Working in binary protects the repetends of 1/3h: Comment on Colussi's 'The convergence classes of Collatz function' |journal=Theoretical Computer Science |doi=10.1016/j.tcs.2015.12.033 |volume=618 |pages=135–141}} 16. ^{{citation | last = Terras | first = Riho | year = 1976 | title = A stopping time problem on the positive integers | journal = Polska Akademia Nauk | mr = 0568274 | volume = 30 | issue = 3 | pages = 241–252 | url = http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/aa/aa30/aa3034.pdf |format=PDF | doi=10.4064/aa-30-3-241-252}} 17. ^{{citation |last=Scollo |first=Giuseppe |year=2007 |contribution=Looking for Class Records in the 3x+1 Problem by means of the COMETA Grid Infrastructure |title=Grid Open Days at the University of Palermo |url=http://www.dmi.unict.it/~scollo/seminars/gridpa2007/CR3x+1paper.pdf}} 18. ^{{citation |last=Conway |first=John H. |year=1972 |contribution=Unpredictable Iterations |title=Proc. 1972 Number Theory Conf., Univ. Colorado, Boulder |pages=49–52}} 19. ^{{cite book |last1=Kurtz |first1=Stuart A. |last2=Simon |first2=Janos |editor1-last=Cai |editor1-first=J.-Y. |editor2-last=Cooper |editor2-first=S. B. |editor3-last=Zhu |editor3-first=H. |year=2007 |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=mhrOkx-xyJIC&pg=PA542 |chapter=The Undecidability of the Generalized Collatz Problem |title=Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Theory and Applications of Models of Computation, TAMC 2007, held in Shanghai, China in May 2007 |isbn=3-540-72503-2 |doi=10.1007/978-3-540-72504-6_49 |pages=542–553}} As PDF 20. ^{{citation |last=Ben-Amram |first=Amir M. |year=2015 |title=Mortality of iterated piecewise affine functions over the integers: Decidability and complexity |journal=Computability |doi=10.3233/COM-150032 |volume=1 |issue=1 |pages=19–56}} 21. ^{{cite book |editor1-last=Lagarias |editor1-first=Jeffrey C. |editor1-link=Jeffrey Lagarias |year=2010 |title=The Ultimate Challenge: the 3x+1 problem |publisher=American Mathematical Society |isbn=978-0-8218-4940-8 |zbl=1253.11003}} 22. ^{{SpringerEOM | urlname=S/s110330 | title=Syracuse problem | author=Jeffrey C. Lagarias}}. 23. ^{{cite journal |first=Marc |last=Chamberland |title=A continuous extension of the 3x + 1 problem to the real line |journal=Dynam. Contin. Discrete Impuls Systems |volume=2 |issue=4 |pages=495–509 |year=1996 |doi= |url=}} 24. ^{{cite journal |last=Garner |first=Lynn E. |year=1981 |title=On the Collatz 3n + 1 Algorithm |journal=Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society |volume=82 |issue=1 |pages=19–22 |doi=10.2307/2044308 |jstor=2044308|accessdate= |quote= }} 25. ^{{cite journal |first=Simon |last=Letherman |first2=Dierk |last2=Schleicher |first3=Reg |last3=Wood |title=The (3n + 1)-Problem and Holomorphic Dynamics |journal=Experimental Mathematics |volume=8 |issue=3 |pages=241–252 |year=1999 |doi= 10.1080/10586458.1999.10504402|url=}} 26. ^Eliahou, Shalom, The 3x+1 problem: new lower bounds on nontrivial cycle lengths, Discrete Mathematics 118 (1993) p. 45-56; Le problème 3n+1 : y a-t-il des cycles non triviaux ?, Images des mathématiques (2011) {{Link language|fr}}. 27. ^{{cite journal |author1=Andrei, Stefan |author2=Masalagiu, Cristian |doi=10.1007/s002360050117 |title=About the Collatz conjecture |year=1998 |journal=Acta Informatica |volume=35 |issue=2 |pages=167–179}} 28. ^{{cite journal |first=Jean Paul |last=Van Bendegem |title=The Collatz Conjecture: A Case Study in Mathematical Problem Solving |journal=Logic and Logical Philosophy |volume=14 |issue= |pages=7–23 |year=2005 |doi= 10.12775/llp.2005.002|url=https://compmath.files.wordpress.com/2008/08/jpvb_collatz.pdf |format=PDF}} 29. ^{{cite book |first=Edward G. |last=Belaga |last2=Mignotte |first2=Maurice |chapter=Walking Cautiously into the Collatz Wilderness: Algorithmically, Number Theoretically, Randomly |chapterurl=http://www-irma.u-strasbg.fr/~belaga/a8*BelagaMathInfo06Presentation060920.ppt |format=PowerPoint |editor= |title=Fourth Colloquium on Mathematics and Computer Science : Algorithms, Trees, Combinatorics and Probabilities, September 18–22, 2006, Institut Élie Cartan, Nancy, France |publisher= |location= |year= |isbn= |pages= |url=}} 30. ^{{cite journal |first=Edward G. |last=Belaga |last2=Mignotte |first2=Maurice |title=Embedding the 3x+1 Conjecture in a 3x+d Context |journal=Experimental Mathematics |volume=7 |issue=2 |pages= |year=1998 |doi= |url=http://www.emis.de/journals/EM/expmath/volumes/7/7.html}} 31. ^1 {{cite book |first=R. P. |last=Steiner |chapter=A theorem on the syracuse problem |chapterurl= |editor= |title=Proceedings of the 7th Manitoba Conference on Numerical Mathematics |publisher= |location= |year=1977 |isbn= |pages=553–9 |url= |mr=535032}} 32. ^1 2 3 {{cite journal |first=J. |last=Simons |first2=B. |last2=de Weger |title=Theoretical and computational bounds for m-cycles of the 3n + 1 problem |journal=Acta Arithmetica |volume=117 |issue=1 |pages=51–70 |year=2003 |doi=10.4064/aa117-1-3 |url=http://deweger.xs4all.nl/papers/%5B35%5DSidW-3n+1-ActaArith%5B2005%5D.pdf |format=PDF|bibcode=2005AcAri.117...51S }} 33. ^Sinyor, J.; "The 3x+1 Problem as a String Rewriting System", International Journal of Mathematics and Mathematical Sciences, volume 2010 (2010), Article ID 458563, 6 pages. 34. ^{{cite paper | author1-link = Edward Belaga | author1-last = Belaga | author1-first = Edward G. | citeseerx = 10.1.1.54.483 | title = Reflecting on the 3x+1 Mystery | publisher = University of Strasbourg | date = 1998 }} 35. ^{{cite arXiv |author=Bruschi, Mario |eprint=0810.5169 |title=A generalization of the Collatz problem and conjecture |class=math.NT |year=2008}} 36. ^{{cite journal | last = De Mol | first = Liesbeth | title = Tag systems and Collatz-like functions | journal = Theoretical Computer Science | volume = 390 | issue = 1 | pages =92–101 | date = January 2008 | url = http://logica.ugent.be/liesbeth/TagColOK.pdf | doi=10.1016/j.tcs.2007.10.020}} 37. ^{{cite arXiv |author=Jeffrey C. Lagarias |eprint=math.NT/0608208 |title=The 3x + 1 problem: An annotated bibliography, II (2000–) |class=math.NT |year=2006}} 38. ^{{cite paper | last1 = Ohira | first1 = Reiko | last2 = Yamashita | first2 = Michinori | url = http://risweb2.ris.ac.jp/faculty/earth_env/yamasita/open/p-col.pdf | title = A generalization of the Collatz problem | language = ja }} 39. ^{{cite paper | first = Matti K. | last = Sinisalo | archivedate = 2009-10-24 | archiveurl = https://web.archive.org/web/20091024183537/http://geocities.com/mattiksinisalo/collatz.doc | url = http://geocities.com/mattiksinisalo/collatz.doc | title = On the minimal cycle lengths of the Collatz sequences | date = June 2003 | publisher = University of Oulu }} 40. ^{{cite paper | first = Paul | last = Stadfeld | url = http://home.versatel.nl/galien8/blueprint/blueprint.html | title = Blueprint for Failure: How to Construct a Counterexample to the Collatz Conjecture }} 41. ^{{cite paper | last = Urata | first = Toshio | url = http://auemath.aichi-edu.ac.jp/~turata/Fall.files/CTZVI.pdf | title = Some Holomorphic Functions connected with the Collatz Problem }}{{dead link|date=August 2016|bot=medic}}{{cbignore|bot=medic}} 42. ^{{cite book | last1=Everest | first1=Graham | last2=van der Poorten | first2=Alf | author2-link=Alfred van der Poorten | last3=Shparlinski | first3=Igor | last4=Ward | first4=Thomas | title=Recurrence sequences | series=Mathematical Surveys and Monographs | volume=104 | location=Providence, Rhode Island, USA | publisher=American Mathematical Society | year=2003 | isbn=0-8218-3387-1 | zbl=1033.11006 | at=Chapter 3.4 }} 43. ^1 {{cite book |last=Guy | first=Richard K. | authorlink=Richard K. Guy | title=Unsolved problems in number theory | publisher=Springer-Verlag |edition=3rd | year=2004 |isbn=0-387-20860-7 | zbl=1058.11001 | chapter="E17: Permutation Sequences" |pages=336–7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1AP2CEGxTkgC&pg=PA337 |ref=harv}} PreprintsBooks[43]}} External links
5 : Articles with inconsistent citation formats|Conjectures|Arithmetic|Integer sequences|Number theory |
|||||||||||||||
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。