请输入您要查询的百科知识:

 

词条 Digital physics
释义

  1. History

     Overview  Weizsäcker's ur-alternatives  Pancomputationalism  Wheeler's "it from bit"  Digital vs. informational physics 

  2. Computational foundations

     Turing machines  The Church–Turing–Deutsch thesis 

  3. Experimental confirmation

  4. Criticism

     Physical symmetries are continuous  Locality 

  5. See also

  6. References

  7. Further reading

  8. External links

In physics and cosmology, digital physics is a collection of theoretical perspectives based on the premise that the universe is describable by information. It is a form of digital ontology about the physical reality. According to this theory, the universe can be conceived of as either the output of a deterministic or probabilistic computer program, a vast, digital computation device, or mathematically isomorphic to such a device.[1]

History

The operations of computers must be compatible with the principles of information theory, statistical thermodynamics, and quantum mechanics. In 1957, a link among these fields was proposed by Edwin Jaynes.[1] He elaborated an interpretation of probability theory as generalized Aristotelian logic, a view linking fundamental physics with digital computers, because these are designed to implement the operations of classical logic and, equivalently, of Boolean algebra.[2]

The hypothesis that the universe is a digital computer was proposed by Konrad Zuse in his book Rechnender Raum (translated into English as Calculating Space). The term digital physics was{{citation needed|date=June 2016}} employed by Edward Fredkin, who later came to prefer the term digital philosophy.[3] Others who have modeled the universe as a giant computer include Stephen Wolfram,[4] Juergen Schmidhuber,[5] and Nobel laureate Gerard 't Hooft.[6] These authors hold that the probabilistic nature of quantum physics is not necessarily incompatible with the notion of computability. Quantum versions of digital physics have recently been proposed by Seth Lloyd[7], Paola Zizzi[8], and Antonio Sciarretta[9].

Related ideas include Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker's binary theory of ur-alternatives, pancomputationalism, computational universe theory, John Archibald Wheeler's "It from bit", and Max Tegmark's ultimate ensemble.

Overview

Digital physics suggests that there exists, at least in principle, a program for a universal computer that computes the evolution of the universe. The computer could be, for example, a huge cellular automaton (Zuse 1967[5][10]), or a universal Turing machine, as suggested by Schmidhuber (1997[5]), who pointed out that there exists a short program that can compute all possible computable universes in an asymptotically optimal way.

Loop quantum gravity could lend support to digital physics, in that it assumes space-time is quantized.[5] Paola Zizzi has formulated a realization of this concept in what has come to be called "computational loop quantum gravity", or CLQG.[11][12] Other theories that combine aspects of digital physics with loop quantum gravity are those of Marzuoli and Rasetti[13][14] and Girelli and Livine.[15]

Weizsäcker's ur-alternatives

Physicist Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker's theory of ur-alternatives (theory of archetypal objects), first publicized in his book The Unity of Nature (1971),[16][17] further developed through the 1990s,[18][19][20] is a kind of digital physics as it axiomatically constructs quantum physics from the distinction between empirically observable, binary alternatives. Weizsäcker used his theory to derive the 3-dimensionality of space and to estimate the entropy of a proton. In 1988 Görnitz has shown that Weizsäcker's assumption can be connected with the Bekenstein-Hawking Entropy.[21]

Pancomputationalism

{{also|Metaphysical naturalism|Mathematicism}}Pancomputationalism (also known as naturalist computationalism)[22] is a view that the universe is a computational machine, or rather a network of computational processes which, following fundamental physical laws, computes (dynamically develops) its own next state from the current one.[23]

A computational universe is proposed by Jürgen Schmidhuber in a paper based on Zuse's 1967 thesis[24]. He pointed out that a simple explanation of the universe would be a Turing machine programmed to execute all possible programs computing all possible histories for all types of computable physical laws. He also pointed out that there is an optimally efficient way of computing all computable universes based on Leonid Levin's universal search algorithm (published in 1973)[25]. In 2000, he expanded this work by combining Ray Solomonoff's theory of inductive inference with the assumption that quickly computable universes are more likely than others. This work on digital physics also led to limit-computable generalizations of algorithmic information or Kolmogorov complexity and the concept of Super Omegas, which are limit-computable numbers that are even more random (in a certain sense) than Gregory Chaitin's number of wisdom Omega.

Wheeler's "it from bit"

Following Jaynes and Weizsäcker, the physicist John Archibald Wheeler proposed an "it from bit" doctrine: information sits at the core of physics, and every "it", whether a particle or field, derives its existence from observations.[26][27][28]

The toughest nut to crack in Wheeler's research program of a digital dissolution of physical being in a unified physics, Wheeler says, is time. In a 1986 eulogy to the mathematician Hermann Weyl, Wheeler proclaimed: "Time, among all concepts in the world of physics, puts up the greatest resistance to being dethroned from ideal continuum to the world of the discrete, of information, of bits. ... Of all obstacles to a thoroughly penetrating account of existence, none looms up more dismayingly than 'time.' Explain time? Not without explaining existence. Explain existence? Not without explaining time. To uncover the deep and hidden connection between time and existence ... is a task for the future."[29][30][31]

Digital vs. informational physics

Not every informational approach to physics (or ontology) is necessarily digital. According to Luciano Floridi,[32] "informational structural realism" is a variant of structural realism that supports an ontological commitment to a world consisting of the totality of informational objects dynamically interacting with each other. Such informational objects are to be understood as constraining affordances.

Pancomputationalists like Lloyd (2006), who models the universe as a quantum computer, can still maintain an analogue or hybrid ontology; and informational ontologists like Kenneth Sayre and Floridi embrace neither a digital ontology nor a pancomputationalist position.[33]

Computational foundations

Turing machines

{{Main|Turing machine}}

The Church–Turing–Deutsch thesis

The classic Church–Turing thesis claims that any computer as powerful as a Turing machine can, in principle, calculate anything that a human can calculate, given enough time. Turing moreover showed that there exist universal Turing machines which can compute anything any other Turing machine can compute—that they are generalizable Turing machines. But the limits of practical computation are set by physics, not by theoretical computer science:

"Turing did not show that his machines can solve any problem that can be solved 'by instructions, explicitly stated rules, or procedures', nor did he prove that the universal Turing machine 'can compute any function that any computer, with any architecture, can compute'. He proved that his universal machine can compute any function that any Turing machine can compute; and he put forward, and advanced philosophical arguments in support of, the thesis here called Turing's thesis. But a thesis concerning the extent of effective methods—which is to say, concerning the extent of procedures of a certain sort that a human being unaided by machinery is capable of carrying out—carries no implication concerning the extent of the procedures that machines are capable of carrying out, even machines acting in accordance with 'explicitly stated rules.' For among a machine's repertoire of atomic operations there may be those that no human being unaided by machinery can perform."[35]

On the other hand, a modification of Turing's assumptions does bring practical computation within Turing's limits; as David Deutsch puts it:

"I can now state the physical version of the Church–Turing principle: 'Every finitely realizable physical system can be perfectly simulated by a universal model computing machine operating by finite means.' This formulation is both better defined and more physical than Turing's own way of expressing it."[36] (Emphasis added)

This compound conjecture is sometimes called the "strong Church–Turing thesis" or the Church–Turing–Deutsch principle. It is stronger because a human or Turing machine computing with pencil and paper (under Turing's conditions) is a finitely realizable physical system.

Experimental confirmation

So far there is no experimental confirmation of either binary or quantized nature of the universe, which are basic for digital physics.

The few attempts made in this direction would include the experiment with holometer designed by Craig Hogan, which among others would detect a bit structure of space-time.[37]

The experiment started collecting data in August 2014.

A new result of the experiment released on December 3, 2015, after a year of data collection, has ruled out Hogan's theory of a pixelated universe to a high degree of statistical significance (4.6 sigma). The study found that space-time is not quantized at the scale being measured.[38]

Criticism

Physical symmetries are continuous

One objection is that extant models of digital physics are incompatible {{Citation needed|date=July 2008}} with the existence of several continuous characters of physical symmetries, e.g., rotational symmetry, translational symmetry, Lorentz symmetry, and the Lie group gauge invariance of Yang-Mills theories, all central to current physical theory.

Proponents of digital physics claim that such continuous symmetries are only convenient (and very good) approximations of a discrete reality. For example, the reasoning leading to systems of natural units and the conclusion that the Planck length is a minimum meaningful unit of distance suggests that at some level, space itself is quantized.[39]

Moreover, computers can manipulate and solve formulas describing real numbers using symbolic computation, thus avoiding the need to approximate real numbers by using an infinite number of digits.

A number—in particular a real number, one with an infinite number of digits—was defined by Turing to be computable if a Turing machine will continue to spit out digits endlessly. In other words, there is no "last digit". But this sits uncomfortably with any proposal that the universe is the output of a virtual-reality exercise carried out in real time (or any plausible kind of time). Known physical laws (including quantum mechanics and its continuous spectra) are very much infused with real numbers and the mathematics of the continuum.

"So ordinary computational descriptions do not have a cardinality of states and state space trajectories that is sufficient for them to map onto ordinary mathematical descriptions of natural systems. Thus, from the point of view of strict mathematical description, the thesis that everything is a computing system in this second sense cannot be supported".[40]

For his part, David Deutsch generally takes a "multiverse" view to the question of continuous vs. discrete. In short, he thinks that “within each universe all observable quantities are discrete, but the multiverse as a whole is a continuum. When the equations of quantum theory describe a continuous but not-directly-observable transition between two values of a discrete quantity, what they are telling us is that the transition does not take place entirely within one universe. So perhaps the price of continuous motion is not an infinity of consecutive actions, but an infinity of concurrent actions taking place across the multiverse.” January, 2001 The Discrete and the Continuous, an abridged version of which appeared in The Times Higher Education Supplement.

Locality

Some argue that extant models of digital physics violate various postulates of quantum physics.[41] For example, if these models are not grounded in Hilbert spaces and probabilities, they belong to the class of theories with local hidden variables that have so far been ruled out experimentally using Bell's theorem. This criticism has two possible answers. First, any notion of locality in the digital model does not necessarily have to correspond to locality formulated in the usual way in the emergent spacetime. A concrete example of this case was given by Lee Smolin.[42]{{specify|date=September 2012}} Another possibility is a well-known loophole in Bell's theorem known as superdeterminism (sometimes referred to as predeterminism).[43] In a completely deterministic model, the experimenter's decision to measure certain components of the spins is predetermined. Thus, the assumption that the experimenter could have decided to measure different components of the spins than he actually did is, strictly speaking, not true.

See also

{{col-begin}}{{col-break}}
  • A New Kind of Science
  • Arthur Eddington
  • Bekenstein bound
  • Bremermann's limit
  • Bousso's holographic bound
  • Bit-string physics
  • Cellular automata
  • Church–Turing thesis
  • Church–Turing–Deutsch principle
  • Clive W. Kilmister
  • Combinatorial hierarchy
  • Combinatorial physics
  • Combinatorics
  • Continuous spatial automata
  • David Deutsch
  • David McGoveran
  • Digital philosophy
  • Digital probabilistic physics
  • Douglas Adams
  • EPR paradox
{{col-break}}
  • The Fabric of Reality
  • Ed Fredkin
  • Frederick Parker-Rhodes
  • Fredkin finite nature hypothesis
  • Gerard 't Hooft
  • H. Pierre Noyes
  • Holographic principle
  • Hypercomputation
  • Information theory
  • Jacob Bekenstein
  • John Stuart Bell
  • John Archibald Wheeler
  • Konrad Zuse
  • Landauer's principle
  • Margolus-Levitin theorem
  • Mathematical universe hypothesis
  • Max Tegmark
  • Tipler's Omega Point
{{col-break}}
  • Programming the Universe
  • Physical information
  • Quantum computation
  • Quantum information
  • Qubit
  • Seth Lloyd
  • Simulation hypothesis
  • Simulated reality
  • Ted Bastin
  • Theory of Everything
  • Ultimate ensemble
  • Wolfram Alpha
{{col-end}}

References

1. ^Jaynes, E. T., 1957, "Information Theory and Statistical Mechanics," Phys. Rev. 106: 620.
Jaynes, E. T., 1957, "Information Theory and Statistical Mechanics II," Phys. Rev. 108: 171.
2. ^Jaynes, E. T., 1990, "Probability Theory as Logic," in Fougere, P.F., ed., Maximum-Entropy and Bayesian Methods. Boston: Kluwer.
3. ^See Fredkin's Digital Philosophy web site.
4. ^A New Kind of Science website. Reviews of ANKS.
5. ^Schmidhuber, J., "Computer Universes and an Algorithmic Theory of Everything"; A Computer Scientist's View of Life, the Universe, and Everything.
6. ^G. 't Hooft, 1999, "[https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9903084 Quantum Gravity as a Dissipative Deterministic System,]" Class. Quantum Grav. 16: 3263–79.
7. ^Lloyd, S., "[https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0501135 The Computational Universe: Quantum gravity from quantum computation.]"
8. ^Zizzi, Paola, "[https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0304032 Spacetime at the Planck Scale: The Quantum Computer View.]"
9. ^Sciarretta, Antonio, "[https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-017-0129-9 A Local-Realistic Model of Quantum Mechanics Based on a Discrete Spacetime.]", Found. Phys. (2018) 48: 60.
10. ^Zuse, Konrad, 1967, Elektronische Datenverarbeitung vol 8., pages 336–344
11. ^Zizzi, Paola, "[https://arxiv.org/gr-qc/0406069 A Minimal Model for Quantum Gravity.]"
12. ^Zizzi, Paola, "[https://arxiv.org/gr-qc/0412076 Computability at the Planck Scale.]"
13. ^Marzuoli, A. and Rasetti, M., 2002, "[https://arxiv.org/quant-ph/0209016 Spin Network Quantum Simulator,]" Phys. Lett. A306, 79–87.
14. ^Marzuoli, A. and Rasetti, M., 2005, "[https://arxiv.org/quant-ph/0410105 Computing Spin Networks,]" Annals of Physics 318: 345–407.
15. ^Girelli, F.; Livine, E. R., 2005, "[https://arxiv.org/gr-qc/0501075]" Class. Quantum Grav. 22: 3295–3314.
16. ^{{cite book |last1=von Weizsäcker |first1= Carl Friedrich |title= Die Einheit der Natur |date=1971 |publisher= Hanser |location=München |isbn= 978-3-446-11479-1}}
17. ^{{cite book | last= von Weizsäcker |first= Carl Friedrich |authorlink= Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker |year= 1980 |title= The Unity of Nature |location= New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux}}
18. ^{{cite book | last= von Weizsäcker | first= Carl Friedrich | authorlink= Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker | year= 1985 | title= Aufbau der Physik | location= Munich | isbn= 978-3-446-14142-1 | language= German}}
19. ^{{cite book|last1=von Weizsäcker|first1=Carl Friedrich |title=The Structure of Physics|date=2006|publisher=Springer|location=Heidelberg|isbn=978-1-4020-5234-7|pages=XXX, 360|edition=Görnitz, Thomas; Lyre, Holger}}
20. ^{{cite book | last= von Weizsäcker | first= Carl Friedrich | authorlink= Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker | year= 1992 | title= Zeit und Wissen | language= German}}
21. ^{{cite journal|last1=Görnitz|first1=Thomas|title=Abstract Quantum Theory and Space-Time Structure I. Ur Theory and Bekenstein-Hawking Entropy|journal=International Journal of Theoretical Physics|date=1988|volume=27|issue=5|pages=527–542|bibcode=1988IJTP...27..527G|doi=10.1007/BF00668835}}
22. ^Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic, [https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.301.4845 "Info‐Computational Philosophy Of Nature: An Informational Universe With Computational Dynamics"] (2011).
23. ^Papers on pancomputationalism on philpapers.org
24. ^Zuse's Thesis
25. ^{{cite journal|last=Levin|first=Leonid|title = Universal search problems (Russian: Универсальные задачи перебора, Universal'nye perebornye zadachi)|journal = Problems of Information Transmission (Russian: Проблемы передачи информации, Problemy Peredachi Informatsii)|volume = 9|issue = 3|pages = 115–116|year = 1973}} (pdf)
26. ^Wheeler, John Archibald; Ford, Kenneth (1998). Geons, Black Holes, and Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics. W. W. Norton & Company {{ISBN|0-393-04642-7}}.
27. ^Wheeler, John A. (1990). "Information, physics, quantum: The search for links". In Zurek, Wojciech Hubert. Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley. {{ISBN|9780201515091}}. OCLC 21482771
28. ^Chalmers, David. J., 1995, "Facing up to the Hard Problem of Consciousness", Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(3): 200–19. This paper cites John A. Wheeler (1990) op. cit. Also see Chalmers, D., 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.
29. ^Wheeler, John Archibald, 1986, "Hermann Weyl and the Unity of Knowledge", American Scientist, 74: 366-375.
30. ^Eldred, Michael, 2009, 'Postscript 2: On quantum physics' assault on time'
31. ^Eldred, Michael, 2009, The Digital Cast of Being: Metaphysics, Mathematics, Cartesianism, Cybernetics, Capitalism, Communication ontos, Frankfurt 2009 137 pp. {{ISBN|978-3-86838-045-3}}
32. ^Floridi, L., 2004, "Informational Realism," in Weckert, J., and Al-Saggaf, Y, eds., Computing and Philosophy Conference, vol. 37."
33. ^See Floridi talk on Informational Nature of Reality, abstract at the E-CAP conference 2006.
34. ^B. Jack Copeland, Computation in Luciano Floridi (ed.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information, Wiley-Blackwell, 2004, ISBN 0-631-22919-1, pp. 10–15
35. ^Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "The Church–Turing thesis" – by B. Jack Copeland.
36. ^David Deutsch, "Quantum Theory, the Church–Turing Principle and the Universal Quantum Computer."
37. ^Andre Salles, "Do we live in a 2-D hologram? New Fermilab experiment will test the nature of the universe", Fermilab Office of Communication, August 26, 2014 
38. ^{{Cite web|url=http://news.fnal.gov/2015/12/holometer-rules-out-first-theory-of-space-time-correlations/|title=Holometer rules out first theory of space-time correlations {{!}} News|website=news.fnal.gov|language=en-US|access-date=2018-10-19}}
39. ^John A. Wheeler, 1990, "Information, physics, quantum: The search for links" in W. Zurek (ed.) Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley.
40. ^Piccinini, Gualtiero, 2007, "Computational Modelling vs. Computational Explanation: Is Everything a Turing Machine, and Does It Matter to the Philosophy of Mind?" Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85(1): 93–115.
41. ^{{cite journal|last=Aaronson|first=Scott|title=Book Review on A New Kind of Science by Stephen Wolfram|journal=Quantum Information and Computation (QIC)|date=September 2002|arxiv=quant-ph/0206089}}
42. ^Lee Smolin, "[https://arxiv.org/abs/hep-th/0201031 Matrix models as non-local hidden variables theories]", 2002; also published in [https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007%2F3-540-26669-0_10 Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics? The Frontiers Collection], Springer, 2005, pp 121-152, {{ISBN|978-3-540-22188-3}}.
43. ^J. S. Bell, 1981, "Bertlmann's socks and the nature of reality," Journal de Physique 42 C2: 41–61.

Further reading

  • Paul Davies, 1992. The Scientific Basis for a Rational World. New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • David Deutsch, 1997. The Fabric of Reality. New York: Allan Lane.
  • Michael Eldred, 2009, The Digital Cast of Being: Metaphysics, Mathematics, Cartesianism, Cybernetics, Capitalism, Communication ontos, Frankfurt 2009, 137 pp. {{ISBN|978-3-86838-045-3}}
  • Edward Fredkin, 1990. "Digital Mechanics," Physica D: 254-70.
  • Seth Lloyd, [https://web.archive.org/web/20080807173904/http://puhep1.princeton.edu/~mcdonald/examples/QM/lloyd_nature_406_1047_00.pdf Ultimate physical limits to computation], Nature, volume 406, pages 1047–1054
  • Mariusz Stanowski, 2014. De Broglie Waves and a Complexity Definition, Infinite Energy, Vol 20, 116 pages 41–45.  
  • Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker,1972. "Die Einheit der Natur", München: Hanser; 1980. The Unity of Nature. New York: Farrar Straus & Giroux.
  • John Archibald Wheeler, 1990. "Information, physics, quantum: The search for links" in W. Zurek (ed.) Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley.
  • John Archibald Wheeler and Kenneth Ford, 1998. Geons, black holes and quantum foam: A life in physics. W. W. Norton. {{ISBN|0-393-04642-7}}.
  • Robert Wright, 1989. Three Scientists and Their Gods: Looking for Meaning in an Age of Information. HarperCollins. {{ISBN|0-06-097257-2}}. This book discusses Edward Fredkin's work.
  • Hector Zenil (ed.), 2012. A Computable Universe: Understanding and Exploring Nature As Computation with a Foreword by Sir Roger Penrose. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company.
  • Konrad Zuse, 1970. Calculating Space. The English translation of his Rechnender Raum.

External links

  • [https://inspirehep.net/record/1387680 Discrete Physics]; Mountain Math Software.
  • Luciano Floridi, "Against Digital Ontology", Synthese, 2009, 168.1, (2009), 151–178.
  • Edward Fredkin:
    • Digital Philosophy
    • Introduction to Digital Philosophy
  • It from bit and fit from bit. On the origin and impact of information in the average evolution (Yves Decadt, 2000). Book published in Dutch with English paper summary in The Information Philosopher, http://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/decadt/
  • Gontigno, Paulo, "Hypercomputation and the Physical Church–Turing thesis"
  • Juergen Schmidhuber:
    • Home page, 1996–2007
    • Computer Universes and Algorithmic Theory of Everything
    • "Zuse's Thesis: The Universe is a Computer"
  • Konrad Zuse, PDF scan of Zuse's paper.
  • Konrad Zuse, Re-edition of Zuse's paper in modern LaTeX.
  • The Oxford Advanced Seminar on Informatic Structures
  • [https://www.wired.com/wired/archive/10.12/holytech.html Wired: God is the Machine]
  • Gualtiero Piccinini. Computation in Physical Systems Discusses the metaphysical foundations of digital physics in section 3.4.
{{Physics-footer}}{{DEFAULTSORT:Digital Physics}}

3 : Digital media|Theoretical physics|Theory of computation

随便看

 

开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。

 

Copyright © 2023 OENC.NET All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/11/17 19:15:46