词条 | 1/3–2/3 conjecture |
释义 |
In order theory, a branch of mathematics, the 1/3–2/3 conjecture states that, if one is comparison sorting a set of items then, no matter what comparisons may have already been performed, it is always possible to choose the next comparison in such a way that it will reduce the number of possible sorted orders by a factor of 2/3 or better. Equivalently, in every finite partially ordered set that is not totally ordered, there exists a pair of elements x and y with the property that at least 1/3 and at most 2/3 of the linear extensions of the partial order place x earlier than y. ExampleThe partial order formed by three elements a, b, and c with a single comparability relationship, {{nowrap|a ≤ b,}} has three linear extensions, {{nowrap|a ≤ b ≤ c,}} {{nowrap|a ≤ c ≤ b,}} and {{nowrap|c ≤ a ≤ b.}} In all three of these extensions, a is earlier than b. However, a is earlier than c in only two of them, and later than c in the third. Therefore, the pair of a and c have the desired property, showing that this partial order obeys the 1/3–2/3 conjecture. This example shows that the constants 1/3 and 2/3 in the conjecture are tight; if q is any fraction strictly between 1/3 and 2/3, then there would not exist a pair x, y in which x is earlier than y in a number of partial orderings that is between q and {{nowrap|1 − q}} times the total number of partial orderings.[1] More generally, let P be any series composition of three-element partial orders and of one-element partial orders, such as the one in the figure. Then P forms an extreme case for the 1/3–2/3 conjecture in the sense that, for each pair x, y of elements, one of the two elements occurs earlier than the other in at most 1/3 of the linear extensions of P. Partial orders with this structure are necessarily series-parallel semiorders; they are the only known extreme cases for the conjecture and can be proven to be the only extreme cases with width two.[2] DefinitionsA partially ordered set is a set X together with a binary relation ≤ that is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive. A total order is a partial order in which every pair of elements is comparable. A linear extension of a finite partial order is a sequential ordering of the elements of X, with the property that if x ≤ y in the partial order, then x must come before y in the linear extension. In other words, it is a total order compatible with the partial order. If a finite partially ordered set is totally ordered, then it has only one linear extension, but otherwise it will have more than one. The 1/3–2/3 conjecture states that one can choose two elements x and y such that, among this set of possible linear extensions, between 1/3 and 2/3 of them place x earlier than y, and symmetrically between 1/3 and 2/3 of them place y earlier {{nowrap|than x.[3]}} There is an alternative and equivalent statement of the 1/3–2/3 conjecture in the language of probability theory. One may define a uniform probability distribution on the linear extensions in which each possible linear extension is equally likely to be chosen. The 1/3–2/3 conjecture states that, under this probability distribution, there exists a pair of elements x and y such that the probability that x is earlier than y in a random linear extension is between 1/3 and 2/3.[3] {{harvtxt|Kahn|Saks|1984}} define δ(P), for any partially ordered set P, to be the largest real number δ such that P has a pair x, y with x earlier than y in a number of linear extensions that is between δ and {{nowrap|1 − δ}} of the total number of linear extensions. In this notation, the 1/3–2/3 conjecture states that every finite partial order that is not total has {{nowrap|δ(P) ≥ 1/3}}.HistoryThe 1/3–2/3 conjecture was formulated by {{harvtxt|Kislitsyn|1968}}, and later made independently by Michael Fredman[3] and by {{harvs|first=Nati|last=Linial|authorlink=Nati Linial|year=1984|txt}}.[4] It was listed as a featured unsolved problem at the founding of the journal Order, and remains unsolved;[4] {{harvtxt|Brightwell|Felsner|Trotter|1995}} call it "one of the most intriguing problems in the combinatorial theory of posets." A survey of the conjecture is given by {{harvtxt|Brightwell|1999}}. Partial resultsThe 1/3–2/3 conjecture is known to be true for certain special classes of partial orders, including partial orders of width two,[5] partial orders of height two,[6] partial orders with at most 11 elements,[7] partial orders in which each element is incomparable to at most six others,[8] series-parallel partial orders,[9] and semiorders.[10] In the limit as n goes to infinity, the proportion of n-element partial orders that obey the 1/3–2/3 conjecture approaches 100%.[7] {{harvtxt|Brightwell|Felsner|Trotter|1995}} proved that, for any finite partial order P that is not total, {{nowrap|δ(P) ≥ 1/2 − {{radic|5}}/10 ≈ 0.276.}} Their results improve previous weaker bounds of the same type.[11] They use the probabilistic interpretation of δ(P) to extend its definition to certain infinite partial orders; in that context, they show that their bounds are optimal, in that there exist infinite partial orders with {{nowrap|1=δ(P) = 1/2 − {{radic|5}}/10.}}Applications{{harvtxt|Kahn|Saks|1984}} proposed the following application for the problem:suppose one wishes to comparison sort a totally ordered set X, for which some partial order information is already known in the form of a partial order on X. In the worst case, each additional comparison between a pair x and y of elements may yield as little information as possible, by resolving the comparison in a way that leaves as many linear extensions as possible compatible with the comparison result. The 1/3–2/3 conjecture states that, at each step, one may choose a comparison to perform that reduces the remaining number of linear extensions by a factor of 2/3; therefore, if there are E linear extensions of the partial order given by the initial information, the sorting problem can be completed in at most log3/2E additional comparisons. However, this analysis neglects the complexity of selecting the optimal pair x and y to compare. Additionally, it may be possible to sort a partial order using a number of comparisons that is better than this analysis would suggest, because it may not be possible for this worst-case behavior to occur at each step of a sorting algorithm. In this direction, it has been conjectured that logφE comparisons may suffice, where φ denotes the golden ratio.[7] A closely related class of comparison sorting problems is considered by {{harvtxt|Fredman|1976}}, among them the problem of comparison sorting a set X when the sorted order of X is known to lie in some set S of permutations of X. Here S is not necessarily generated as the set of linear extensions of a partial order. Despite this added generality, Fredman shows that X can be sorted using log2|S| + O(|X|) comparisons. This same bound applies as well to the case of partial orders and shows that log2E + O(n) comparisons suffice. Generalizations and related results{{harvtxt|Kahn|Saks|1984}} conjectured that, in the limit as w tends to infinity, the value of δ(P) for partially ordered sets of width w should tend to 1/2. In particular, they expect that only partially ordered sets of width two can achieve the worst case value {{nowrap|1=δ(P) = 1/3,}} and {{harvtxt|Aigner|1985}} stated this explicitly as a conjecture. The smallest known value of δ(P) for posets of width three is 14/39,[12] and computer searches have shown that no smaller value is possible for width-3 posets with nine or fewer elements.[6]Marcin Peczarski[7][8] has formulated a "gold partition conjecture" stating that in each partial order that is not a total order one can find two consecutive comparisons such that, if ti denotes the number of linear extensions remaining after i of the comparisons have been made, then (in each of the four possible outcomes of the comparisons) {{nowrap|t0 ≥ t1 + t2.}} If this conjecture is true, it would imply the 1/3–2/3 conjecture: the first of the two comparisons must be between a pair that splits the remaining comparisons by at worst a 1/3–2/3 ratio. The gold partition conjecture would also imply that a partial order with E linear extensions can be sorted in at most logφE comparisons; the name of the conjecture is derived from this connection with the golden ratio. It is #P-complete, given a finite partial order P and a pair of elements x and y, to calculate the proportion of the linear extensions of P that place x earlier than y.[13] Notes1. ^{{harvtxt|Kahn|Saks|1984}}; {{harvtxt|Brightwell|Felsner|Trotter|1995}}. 2. ^{{harvtxt|Aigner|1985}}. 3. ^However, despite the close connection of {{harvtxt|Fredman|1976}} to the problem of sorting partially ordered data and hence to the 1/3–2/3 conjecture, it is not mentioned in that paper. 4. ^1 2 3 {{harvtxt|Brightwell|Felsner|Trotter|1995}}. 5. ^{{harvtxt|Linial|1984}}, Theorem 2. 6. ^1 {{harvtxt|Trotter|Gehrlein|Fishburn|1992}}. 7. ^1 2 3 {{harvtxt|Peczarski|2006}}. 8. ^1 {{harvtxt|Peczarski|2008}}. 9. ^{{harvtxt|Zaguia|2012}} 10. ^{{harvtxt|Brightwell|1989}}. 11. ^{{harvtxt|Kahn|Saks|1984}}; {{harvtxt|Khachiyan|1989}}; {{harvtxt|Kahn|Linial|1991}}; {{harvtxt|Felsner|Trotter|1993}}. 12. ^{{harvtxt|Saks|1985}}. 13. ^{{harvtxt|Brightwell|Winkler|1991}}. References
| last = Aigner | first = Martin | authorlink = Martin Aigner | doi = 10.1007/BF00333131 | issue = 3 | journal = Order | pages = 257–264 | title = A note on merging | volume = 2 | year = 1985| doi-broken-date = 2019-03-06 }}.
| last = Brightwell | first = Graham R. | doi = 10.1007/BF00353656 | issue = 4 | journal = Order | pages = 369–380 | title = Semiorders and the 1/3–2/3 conjecture | volume = 5 | year = 1989}}.
| last = Brightwell | first = Graham R. | doi = 10.1016/S0012-365X(98)00311-2 | issue = 1–3 | journal = Discrete Mathematics | pages = 25–52 | title = Balanced pairs in partial orders | volume = 201 | year = 1999}}.
| last1 = Brightwell | first1 = Graham R. | last2 = Felsner | first2 = Stefan | last3 = Trotter | first3 = William T. | doi = 10.1007/BF01110378 | mr = 1368815 | issue = 4 | journal = Order | pages = 327–349 | title = Balancing pairs and the cross product conjecture | volume = 12 | year = 1995| citeseerx = 10.1.1.38.7841
| last1 = Brightwell | first1 = Graham R. | last2 = Winkler | first2 = Peter | author2-link = Peter Winkler | doi = 10.1007/BF00383444 | issue = 3 | journal = Order | pages = 225–242 | title = Counting linear extensions | volume = 8 | year = 1991}}.
| last1 = Felsner | first1 = Stefan | last2 = Trotter | first2 = William T. | contribution = Balancing pairs in partially ordered sets | mr = 1249709 | location = Budapest | pages = 145–157 | publisher = János Bolyai Mathematical Society | series = Bolyai Society Mathematical Studies | title = Combinatorics, Paul Erdős is eighty | volume = 1 | year = 1993}}.
| last = Fredman | first = M. L. | authorlink = Michael Fredman | doi = 10.1016/0304-3975(76)90078-5 | issue = 4 | journal = Theoretical Computer Science | pages = 355–361 | title = How good is the information theory bound in sorting? | volume = 1 | year = 1976}}
| last1 = Kahn | first1 = Jeff | last2 = Linial | first2 = Nati | author2-link = Nati Linial | doi = 10.1007/BF01275670 | issue = 4 | journal = Combinatorica | pages = 363–368 | title = Balancing extensions via Brunn-Minkowski | volume = 11 | year = 1991}}.
| last1 = Kahn | first1 = Jeff | last2 = Saks | first2 = Michael | author2-link = Michael Saks (mathematician) | doi = 10.1007/BF00565647 | issue = 2 | journal = Order | pages = 113–126 | title = Balancing poset extensions | volume = 1 | year = 1984}}.
| last = Khachiyan | first = Leonid | authorlink = Leonid Khachiyan | contribution = Optimal algorithms in convex programming decomposition and sorting | editor-last = Jaravlev | editor-first = J. | language = Russian | location = Moscow | pages = 161–205 | publisher = Nauka | title = Computers and Decision Problems | year = 1989}}. As cited by {{harvtxt|Brightwell|Felsner|Trotter|1995}}.
| last = Kislitsyn | first = S. S. | doi = 10.1007/BF01111312 | issue = 5 | journal = Mathematical Notes | pages = 798–801 | title = A finite partially ordered set and its corresponding set of permutations | volume = 4 | year = 1968}}.
| last = Linial | first = Nati | authorlink = Nati Linial | doi = 10.1137/0213049 | issue = 4 | journal = SIAM Journal on Computing | pages = 795–801 | title = The information-theoretic bound is good for merging | volume = 13 | year = 1984}}.
| last = Peczarski | first = Marcin | doi = 10.1007/s11083-006-9033-1 | issue = 1 | journal = Order | pages = 89–95 | title = The gold partition conjecture | volume = 23 | year = 2006}}.
| last = Peczarski | first = Marcin | doi = 10.1007/s11083-008-9081-9 | issue = 2 | journal = Order | pages = 91–103 | title = The gold partition conjecture for 6-thin posets | volume = 25 | year = 2008}}.
| last = Saks | first = Michael | authorlink = Michael Saks (mathematician) | title = Balancing linear extensions of ordered sets | department = Unsolved problems | doi = 10.1007/BF00333138| journal = Order | pages = 327–330 | volume = 2 | year = 1985| doi-broken-date = 2019-03-06 }}
| last1 = Trotter | first1 = William T. | last2 = Gehrlein | first2 = William V. | last3 = Fishburn | first3 = Peter C. | author3-link = Peter C. Fishburn | doi = 10.1007/BF00419038 | issue = 1 | journal = Order | pages = 43–53 | title = Balance theorems for height-2 posets | volume = 9 | year = 1992}}.
| last1 = Zaguia| first1 = Imed | issue = 2 | journal = Electronic Journal of Combinatorics | pages = P29 | title = The 1/3-2/3 Conjecture for N-free ordered sets | url = http://www.combinatorics.org/ojs/index.php/eljc/article/view/v19i2p29 | volume = 19 | year = 2012}}.{{DEFAULTSORT:1 3-2 3 conjecture}} 2 : Order theory|Conjectures |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。