请输入您要查询的百科知识:

 

词条 Gilbert Ryle
释义

  1. Life

  2. Work

     The Concept of Mind  Philosophy as cartography  Knowing-how and knowing-that 

  3. Legacy

  4. Books

  5. References

  6. External links

{{EngvarB|date=August 2014}}{{Use dmy dates|date=August 2014}}{{Infobox philosopher
|region = Western philosophy
|era = 20th-century philosophy
|image =Rex Whistler - Gilbert Ryle, Fellow.jpg
|caption =Portrait by Rex Whistler
|name = Gilbert Ryle
|birth_date = 19 August 1900
|birth_place = Brighton, England
|death_date = 6 October 1976 (aged 76)
|death_place = Whitby, England
|alma_mater = The Queen's College, Oxford
|school_tradition = Analytic
Logical behaviorism[1][2]
|notable_students = G. A. Cohen
|main_interests = Language, ordinary language philosophy, philosophy of mind, behaviourism, meaning, cognition
|influences = René Descartes, Arthur Schopenhauer, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Herbert James Paton,[3] Edmund Husserl[4]
|influenced = J. L. Austin, A. J. Ayer, John Searle, R. M. Hare, Wilfrid Sellars, Daniel Dennett, Richard Webster, Ullin Place, Clifford Geertz, G. A. Cohen, P. F. Strawson, Michael Dummett[5]
|notable_ideas = Category mistake, Ryle's Regress, ordinary language philosophy, ghost in the machine, thick description, knowing-how vs. knowing-that, topic neutrality[6]
}}Gilbert Ryle (19 August 1900 – 6 October 1976) was a British philosopher.[7] He was a representative of the generation of British ordinary language philosophers who shared Ludwig Wittgenstein's approach to philosophical problems,[8] and is principally known for his critique of Cartesian dualism, for which he coined the phrase "the ghost in the machine." Some of his ideas in the philosophy of mind have been referred to as "behaviourist". Ryle's best known book is The Concept of Mind (1949), in which he writes that the "general trend of this book will undoubtedly, and harmlessly, be stigmatised as 'behaviourist'."[9] Ryle, having engaged in detailed study of the key works of Bernard Bolzano, Franz Brentano, Alexius Meinong, Edmund Husserl, and Martin Heidegger, himself suggested instead that the book "could be described as a sustained essay in phenomenology, if you are at home with that label."[10]

Life

Ryle was born in Brighton, England, in 1900, and grew up in an environment of learning. His father, Reginald John Ryle, was a Brighton doctor, a generalist who had interests in philosophy and astronomy, and passed on to his children an impressive library. He was a son of John Charles Ryle, first Anglican Bishop of Liverpool.[11][12] The Ryle family were Cheshire landed gentry; Gilbert's elder brother, John Alfred Ryle, of Barkhale, Sussex, became head of the family. Their ancestor, John Ryle, a silk merchant, was a friend of the theologian and evangelist John Wesley; members of this Ryle family include the silk manufacturer ('father of the United States silk industry') John Ryle and his nephew and business partner William. Gilbert Ryle's mother, Catherine, was daughter of Samuel King Scott (younger brother of the architect Sir George Gilbert Scott) by his wife Georgina, daughter of William Hulme Bodley, M.D. and sister of architect George Frederick Bodley, himself a student of Sir George Gilbert Scott. Cousins of the Ryle family thus included the haematologist Ronald Bodley Scott, architect George Gilbert Scott Jr., founder of Watts & Co., and his son, Giles Gilbert Scott, designer of the Battersea Power Station.[13]

Ryle was educated at Brighton College, and in 1919 he went up to The Queen's College at Oxford to study classics but was quickly drawn to philosophy. He graduated with a "triple first": first-class honours in classical honour moderations (1921), literae humaniores (1923), and philosophy, politics, and economics (1924), and was appointed as lecturer in philosophy at Christ Church, Oxford, in 1925. A year later, he became a Student (Fellow) and tutor at Christ Church, where he remained until 1940.[14]

In the Second World War he was commissioned in the Welsh Guards. A capable linguist, he was recruited into intelligence work and by the end of the war had been promoted to the rank of Major. After the war he returned to Oxford and was elected Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy and Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. He published his principal work, The Concept of Mind in 1949. He was President of the Aristotelian Society from 1945 to 1946, and editor of the philosophical journal Mind from 1947 to 1971. Ryle died on 6 October 1976 at Whitby, North Yorkshire.[14]

His brothers John Alfred (1889–1950) and George Bodley (1902–1978), both educated at Brighton College as well, also had eminent careers. John became Regius Professor of Physic at the University of Cambridge 1935–1945 and physician to King George V. George, after serving as Director of Forestry first for Wales and then England, was Deputy-Director of the Forestry Commission 1963–1965 and appointed a CBE.{{citation needed|date=January 2019}}

Work

The Concept of Mind

{{Main|The Concept of Mind}}

In The Concept of Mind, Ryle argues that dualism involves category mistakes and philosophical nonsense. Category mistakes and nonsense as philosophical topics continued to inform Ryle's work. Students in his 1967-8 Oxford audience would be asked rhetorically what was wrong with saying that there are three things in a field: two cows and a pair of cows. They were also invited to ponder whether the bung-hole of a beer barrel is part of the barrel or not.[15]

Philosophy as cartography

{{cquote|The philosophical arguments which constitute this book are intended not to increase what we know about minds but to rectify the logical geography of the knowledge we already possess.[16]}}

Ryle thought it was no longer possible to believe that it was a philosopher's task to study mental as opposed to physical objects. However, in its place, Ryle saw the tendency of philosophers to search for objects whose nature was neither physical nor mental. Ryle believed, instead, that "philosophical problems are problems of a certain sort; they are not problems of an ordinary sort about special entities."[14]

Ryle offers the analogy of philosophy as being like cartography. Competent speakers of a language, Ryle believes, are to a philosopher what ordinary villagers are to a mapmaker. The ordinary villager has a competent grasp of his village, and is familiar with its inhabitants and geography. However, when asked to interpret a map for the same knowledge he has practically, the villager will have difficulty until he is able to translate his practical knowledge into universal cartographal terms. The villager thinks of the village in personal and practical terms, while the mapmaker thinks of the village in neutral, public, cartographical terms.[17]

By "mapping" the words and phrases of a particular statement, philosophers are able to generate what Ryle calls "implication threads." In other words, each word or phrase of a statement contributes to the statement in that, if the words or phrases were changed, the statement would have a different implication. The philosopher must show the directions and limits of different implication threads that a "concept contributes to the statements in which it occurs." To show this, he must be "tugging" at neighbouring threads, which, in turn, must also be "tugging." Philosophy, then, searches for the meaning of these implication threads in the statements in which they are used.[18]

Knowing-how and knowing-that

{{main|Descriptive knowledge|Procedural knowledge}}

A distinction deployed in The Concept of Mind, between knowing-how and knowing-that (e.g., knowing how to tie a reef knot and knowing that Queen Victoria died in 1901), has attracted independent interest.[19] This distinction is also the origin of procedural (knowing-how) and declarative (knowing-that) models of long term memory.

Ryle took a narrow view of the scope of his field. For him, philosophy did not extend beyond the philosophy of mind, philosophical logic, and the philosophy of language. Ethics, political philosophy, and aesthetics were 'philosophy' only by a strained courtesy and a burdensome historical tradition.[20]

Legacy

Ryle's notion of thick description, from "The Thinking of Thoughts: What is 'Le Penseur' Doing?"[21] and "Thinking and Reflecting", has been an important influence on cultural anthropologists such as Clifford Geertz.[22]

[23]

The Concept of Mind was recognised on its appearance as an important contribution to philosophical psychology, and an important work in the ordinary language philosophy movement. However, in the 1960s and 1970s the rising influence of the cognitivist theories of Noam Chomsky, Herbert A. Simon, Jerry Fodor and others in the neo-Cartesian school became predominant. Chomsky even wrote a book entitled Cartesian Linguistics. The two major post-War schools in the philosophy of mind, the representationalism of Jerry Fodor and the functionalism of Wilfrid Sellars, posited precisely the 'internal' cognitive states that Ryle had argued against. However, as influential modern philosopher and former student Daniel Dennett has pointed out, recent trends in psychology such as embodied cognition, discursive psychology, situated cognition and others in the post-cognitivist tradition have provoked a renewed interest in Ryle's work. Dennett has provided a sympathetic foreword to the 2000 edition of The Concept of Mind.[24] Ryle remains a significant defender of the possibility of lucid and meaningful interpretation of higher-level human activities without recourse to an immaterial soul.

Richard Webster endorsed Ryle's arguments against mentalist philosophies, suggesting that they implied that "theories of human nature which repudiate the evidence of behaviour and refer solely or primarily to invisible mental events will never in themselves be able to unlock the most significant mysteries of human nature."[25]

Books

  • The Concept of Mind (1949)
  • Dilemmas. The Tarner Lectures 1953 (1954), a collection of shorter pieces
  • Plato's Progress (1966)
  • Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy (1977), editor
  • On Thinking (1979)[26]

References

1. ^{{cite SEP |url-id=behaviorism |title=Behaviorism}}
2. ^Neil Tennant, Introducing Philosophy: God, Mind, World, and Logic, Routledge, 2015, p. 299.
3. ^Stuart Brown, Diane Collinson, Robert Wilkinson (eds), Biographical Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Philosophers, Routledge, 2012: "Paton, Herbert James."
4. ^Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, Volume 1, Routledge & Keegan Paul, 2001: Introduction by Dermot Moran, p. lxiv: "Husserl... visited England in 1922 intent on establishing relations with English philosopherss.... He delivered a number of lectures which were attended by Gilbert Ryle...."
5. ^Michael Dummett, Origins of Analytical Philosophy, Bloombury, 2014, p. xiii; Anat Biletzki, Anat Matarp (eds.), The Story of Analytic Philosophy: Plot and Heroes, Routledge, 2002, p. 57: "It was Gilbert Ryle who, [Dummett] says, opened his eyes to this fact in his lectures on Bolzano, Brentano, Meinong, and Husserl."
6. ^Logical Constants (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
7. ^{{Cite news|url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Gilbert-Ryle|title=Gilbert Ryle {{!}} British philosopher|work=Encyclopedia Britannica|access-date=2018-09-03|language=en}}
8. ^A. C. Grayling (Wittgenstein, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1988, p.114) is certain that, despite the fact that Wittgenstein's work might have possibly played some "second or third-hand [part in the promotion of] the philosophical concern for language which was dominant in the mid-century", neither Gilbert Ryle nor any of those in the so-called "Ordinary language philosophy" school that is chiefly associated with J. L. Austin (and, according to Grayling, G. E. Moore, C. D. Broad, Bertrand Russell and A. J. Ayer) were Wittgensteinians. Grayling asserts that "most of them were largely unaffected by Wittgenstein's later ideas, and some were actively hostile to them"
9. ^Ryle, Gilbert.The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002. Pp. 327.
10. ^Gilbert Ryle, "Phenomenology versus The Concept of Mind," in Collected Papers, London: Hutchinson, 1971, p. 188.
11. ^Ryle ('Modern Studies in Philosophy' series), ed. Oscar P. Wood and George Pitcher, Doubleday & Co. Ltd, 1970, p. 1
12. ^Faith in the Age of Science: Atheism, Religion, and the Big Yellow Crane, Mark Silversides, Sacristy Press, 2012, p. 157
13. ^Burke's Landed Gentry, 18th edition, vol. 1, 1965, ed. Peter Townend, p. 615, 'Ryle formerly of Barkhale' pedigree
14. ^{{cite encyclopedia| last = Tanney | first = Julia | title = Gilbert Ryle | encyclopedia = Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | publisher = The Metaphysics Research Lab | location = Stanford, CA | date = Winter 2003 | url = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ryle/ | accessdate = 5 March 2008 }}
15. ^{{Cite web|url=https://www.the-philosophy.com/ryle-concept-mind-summary|title=Ryle: The concept of mind (Summary)|website=www.the-philosophy.com|language=en-US|access-date=2018-09-03}}
16. ^Concept of Mind p 1
17. ^{{cite journal | last = Ryle | first = Gilbert | authorlink = | author2 = | title = Abstractions | journal = Collected Papers | volume = 2 | issue = | pages = 440–442 | publisher = Hutchinson | location = London | year = 1971 | url = | format = | issn = | accessdate = }}
18. ^{{cite journal | last = Ryle | first = Gilbert | authorlink = | author2 = | title = Abstractions | journal = Collected Papers | volume = 2 | issue = | pages = 444–445 | publisher = Hutchinson | location = London | year = 1971 | url = | format = | issn = | accessdate = }}
19. ^Jason Stanley and Timothy Williamson, "Knowing How", Journal of Philosophy, 98(8): 411–444, 2001.
20. ^{{Cite web|url=https://www.philosophybasics.com/philosophers_ryle.html|title=Gilbert Ryle > By Individual Philosopher > Philosophy|website=www.philosophybasics.com|language=en|access-date=2018-09-03}}
21. ^{{Cite news | last =Ryle | first =Gilbert | author-link = | year =1968|title=The Thinking of Thoughts: What is 'Le Penseur' Doing?|url=http://lucy.ukc.ac.uk/CSACSIA/Vol11/Papers/ryle_1.html|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080410232658/http://lucy.ukc.ac.uk/CSACSIA/Vol11/Papers/ryle_1.html|archive-date=2008-04-10 | accessdate =25 June 2008 | periodical =University Lectures | place=University of Saskatchewan | number =18}} Reprinted in his {{Cite book | year =1971 | title =Collected Papers | publication-place =London | publisher =Hutchinson | volume =2 | pages =480–496|postscript=none}}, and (linked) in {{Cite news | publication-date =21 August 1996 | periodical =Studies in Anthropology | volume =11 | publisher =Centre for Social Anthropology and Computing | issn =1363-1098}}
22. ^{{Cite book | last = Geertz | first = Clifford | author-link = Clifford Geertz | publication-date = 1973 | chapter = Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture | chapterurl = http://hypergeertz.jku.at/geertztexts/thick_description.htm | date = | year = | place = | title = The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays | publication-place = New-York | publisher = Basic Books | pages = 3–30 | accessdate = 25 June 2008}}
23. ^{{cite journal|title=Gilbert Ryle|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ryle/#Thi|journal=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}}
24. ^{{cite journal|url = http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/2002/Dennett.html|last = Dennett|first = Daniel C.|journal = Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy|issue = 7|year = 2002|title = Re-Introducing The Concept of Mind|authorlink = Daniel Dennett|accessdate = 20 December 2007}}
25. ^{{cite book |author=Webster, Richard |title=Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science and Psychoanalysis |publisher=The Orwell Press |location=Oxford |year=2005 |pages=vii, 483 |isbn=0951592254 |oclc= |doi= |accessdate=}}
26. ^{{Cite web|url=http://www.linacre.ox.ac.uk/facilities/library/gilbert-ryle-collection|title=Gilbert Ryle Collection {{!}} Linacre College|website=www.linacre.ox.ac.uk|language=en|access-date=2018-09-03}}

External links

{{wikiquote}}
  • Gilbert Ryle in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Gilbert Ryle at PhilosophyPages.com
  • About Ryle's Concept of Mind
  • Ordinary Language, the Philosophical Review LXII (1953)
  • [https://www.sfu.ca/~jeffpell/Phil467/RyleUseUsage61.pdf Symposium: Use, Usage and Meaning]. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 35 (1961): 223–242. (with J. N. Findlay)
  • The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy – Issue dedicated to Ryle
  • Profile at UXL Newsmakers {{dead link|date=October 2013}}
  • The Gilbert Ryle Collection at Linacre College, Oxford. Linacre College houses Gilbert Ryle's library along with a collection of his papers.
  • [https://www.nytimes.com/1976/10/20/archives/gilbert-ryle-british-philosopher-of-mind-dead-in-yorkshire-at-76.html Gilbert Ryle, British ‘Philosopher Of Mind,’ Dead in Yorkshire at 76] New York Times obituary
{{Analytic philosophy}}{{Metaphysics}}{{Epistemology}}{{philosophy of language}}{{philosophy of mind}}{{Authority control}}{{DEFAULTSORT:Ryle, Gilbert}}

24 : 1900 births|1976 deaths|20th-century British philosophers|20th-century English writers|Alumni of The Queen's College, Oxford|Analytic philosophers|Aristotelian philosophers|English philosophers|Epistemologists|Fellows of Christ Church, Oxford|Fellows of Magdalen College, Oxford|Linguistic turn|Metaphysicians|Ontologists|Ordinary language philosophy|People educated at Brighton College|People from Brighton|Phenomenologists|Philosophers of language|Philosophers of mind|Philosophy academics|Presidents of the Aristotelian Society|Waynflete Professors of Metaphysical Philosophy|Wittgensteinian philosophers

随便看

 

开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。

 

Copyright © 2023 OENC.NET All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/9/29 15:32:38