词条 | Fermat's Last Theorem | ||
释义 |
In number theory Fermat's Last Theorem (sometimes called Fermat's conjecture, especially in older texts) states that no three positive integers {{math|a}}, {{math|b}}, and {{math|c}} satisfy the equation {{math|1=an + bn = cn}} for any integer value of {{math|n}} greater than 2. The cases {{math|1=n = 1}} and {{math|1=n = 2}} have been known since antiquity to have an infinite number of solutions.[1] The proposition was first conjectured by Pierre de Fermat in 1637 in the margin of a copy of Arithmetica; Fermat added that he had a proof that was too large to fit in the margin. After 358 years of effort by mathematicians, the first successful proof was released in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, and formally published in 1995; it was described as a 'stunning advance' in the citation for Wiles' Abel Prize award in 2016.[2] It also proved much of the modularity theorem and opened up entire new approaches to numerous other problems and mathematically powerful modularity lifting techniques. The unsolved problem stimulated the development of algebraic number theory in the 19th century and the proof of the modularity theorem in the 20th century. It is among the most notable theorems in the history of mathematics and prior to its proof was in the Guinness Book of World Records as the "most difficult mathematical problem" in part because the theorem has the largest number of unsuccessful proofs.[3] {{TOC limit|3}}OverviewPythagorean originsThe Pythagorean equation, {{nowrap|1=x2 + y2 = z2}}, has an infinite number of positive integer solutions for x, y, and z; these solutions are known as Pythagorean triples. Around 1637, Fermat wrote in the margin of a book that the more general equation {{nowrap|1=an + bn = cn}} had no solutions in positive integers if n is an integer greater than 2. Although he claimed to have a general proof of his conjecture, Fermat left no details of his proof, and no proof by him has ever been found. His claim was discovered some 30 years later, after his death. This claim, which came to be known as Fermat's Last Theorem, stood unsolved for the next three and a half centuries. The claim eventually became one of the most notable unsolved problems of mathematics. Attempts to prove it prompted substantial development in number theory, and over time Fermat's Last Theorem gained prominence as an unsolved problem in mathematics. Subsequent developments and solutionThe special case {{math|1=n = 4}} - proved by Fermat himself - is sufficient to establish that if the theorem is false for some exponent n that is not a prime number, it must also be false for some smaller n, so only prime values of n need further investigation[4]. Over the next two centuries (1637–1839), the conjecture was proved for only the primes 3, 5, and 7, although Sophie Germain innovated and proved an approach that was relevant to an entire class of primes. In the mid-19th century, Ernst Kummer extended this and proved the theorem for all regular primes, leaving irregular primes to be analyzed individually. Building on Kummer's work and using sophisticated computer studies, other mathematicians were able to extend the proof to cover all prime exponents up to four million, but a proof for all exponents was inaccessible (meaning that mathematicians generally considered a proof impossible, exceedingly difficult, or unachievable with current knowledge).{{citation needed|date = March 2016}} Separately, around 1955, Japanese mathematicians Goro Shimura and Yutaka Taniyama suspected a link might exist between elliptic curves and modular forms, two completely different areas of mathematics. Known at the time as the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, and (eventually) as the modularity theorem, it stood on its own, with no apparent connection to Fermat's Last Theorem. It was widely seen as significant and important in its own right, but was (like Fermat's theorem) widely considered completely inaccessible to proof.{{citation needed|date = March 2016}} In 1984, Gerhard Frey noticed an apparent link between these two previously unrelated and unsolved problems. An outline suggesting this could be proved was given by Frey. The full proof that the two problems were closely linked was accomplished in 1986 by Ken Ribet, building on a partial proof by Jean-Pierre Serre, who proved all but one part known as the "epsilon conjecture" (see: Ribet's Theorem and Frey curve).[2] These papers by Frey, Serre and Ribet showed that if the Modularity Theorem could be proven for at least the semi-stable class of elliptic curves, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem would also follow automatically. The connection is described below: any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the Modularity Theorem. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then by definition no solution contradicting Fermat's Last Theorem could exist, which would therefore have to be true as well. Although both problems were daunting and widely considered to be "completely inaccessible" to proof at the time,[2] this was the first suggestion of a route by which Fermat's Last Theorem could be extended and proved for all numbers, not just some numbers. Also important for researchers choosing a research topic was the fact that unlike Fermat's Last Theorem the Modularity Theorem was a major active research area for which a proof was widely desired and not just a historical oddity, so time spent working on it could be justified professionally.[5] However, general opinion was that this simply showed the impracticality of proving the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture.[6] Mathematician John Coates' quoted reaction was a common one: "I myself was very sceptical that the beautiful link between Fermat’s Last Theorem and the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture would actually lead to anything, because I must confess I did not think that the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture was accessible to proof. Beautiful though this problem was, it seemed impossible to actually prove. I must confess I thought I probably wouldn’t see it proved in my lifetime." [6] On hearing that Ribet had proven Frey's link to be correct, English mathematician Andrew Wiles, who had a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem and had a background of working with elliptic curves and related fields, decided to try to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture as a way to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. In 1993, after six years of working secretly on the problem, Wiles succeeded in proving enough of the conjecture to prove Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles's paper was massive in size and scope. A flaw was discovered in one part of his original paper during peer review and required a further year and collaboration with a past student, Richard Taylor, to resolve. As a result, the final proof in 1995 was accompanied by a smaller joint paper showing that the fixed steps were valid. Wiles's achievement was reported widely in the popular press, and was popularized in books and television programs. The remaining parts of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, now proven and known as the Modularity theorem, were subsequently proved by other mathematicians, who built on Wiles's work between 1996 and 2001.{{citation needed|date = March 2016}} For his proof, Wiles was honoured and received numerous awards, including the 2016 Abel Prize.[7][8][9] Equivalent statements of the theoremThere are several alternative ways to state Fermat's Last Theorem that are mathematically equivalent to the original statement of the problem. In order to state them, we use mathematical notation: let {{math|1=N}} be the set of natural numbers 1, 2, 3, ..., let {{math|1=Z}} be the set of integers 0, ±1, ±2, ..., and let {{math|1=Q}} be the set of rational numbers {{sfrac|a|b}} where {{math|1=a}} and {{math|1=b}} are in {{math|1=Z}} with {{math|1=b}}≠0. In what follows we will call a solution to {{math|1=xn + yn {{=}} zn}} where one or more of {{math|1=x}}, {{math|1=y}}, or {{math|1=z}} is zero a trivial solution. A solution where all three are non-zero will be called a non-trivial solution. For comparison's sake we start with the original formulation.
Most popular treatments of the subject state it this way. In contrast, almost all mathematics textbooks state it over {{math|1=Z}}:{{CN|date=August 2018}}
The equivalence is clear if {{math|1=n}} is even. If {{math|1=n}} is odd and all three of {{math|1=x, y, z}} are negative then we can replace {{math|1=x, y, z}} with {{math|1=−x, −y, −z}} to obtain a solution in {{math|1=N}}. If two of them are negative, it must be {{math|1=x}} and {{math|1=z}} or {{math|1=y}} and {{math|1=z}}. If {{math|1=x, z}} are negative and {{math|1=y}} is positive, then we can rearrange to get {{math|1=(−z)n + yn {{=}} (−x)n}} resulting in a solution in {{math|1=N}}; the other case is dealt with analogously. Now if just one is negative, it must be {{math|1=x}} or {{math|1=y}}. If {{math|1=x}} is negative, and {{math|1=y}} and {{math|1=z}} are positive, then it can be rearranged to get {{math|1=(−x)n + zn {{=}} yn}} again resulting in a solution in {{math|1=N}}; if {{math|1=y}} is negative, the result follows symmetrically. Thus in all cases a nontrivial solution in {{math|1=Z}} would also mean a solution exists in {{math|1=N}}, the original formulation of the problem.
This is because the exponent of {{math|1=x, y}} and {{math|1=z}} are equal (to {{math|1=n}}), so if there is a solution in {{math|1=Q}} then it can be multiplied through by an appropriate common denominator to get a solution in {{math|1=Z}}, and hence in {{math|1=N}}.
A non-trivial solution {{math|1=a}}, {{math|1=b}}, {{math|1=c}} ∈ {{math|1=Z}} to {{math|1=xn + yn {{=}} zn}} yields the non-trivial solution {{sfrac|a|c}}, {{sfrac|b|c}} ∈ {{math|1=Q}} for {{math|1=vn + wn {{=}} 1}}. Conversely, a solution {{sfrac|a|b}}, {{sfrac|c|d}} ∈ {{math|1=Q}} to {{math|1=vn + wn {{=}} 1}} yields the non-trivial solution {{math|1=ad, cb, bd}} for {{math|1=xn + yn {{=}} zn}}. This last formulation is particularly fruitful, because it reduces the problem from a problem about surfaces in three dimensions to a problem about curves in two dimensions. Furthermore, it allows working over the field {{math|1=Q}}, rather than over the ring {{math|1=Z}}; fields exhibit more structure than rings, which allows for deeper analysis of their elements.
Examining this elliptic curve with Ribet's theorem shows that it does not have a modular form. However, the proof by Andrew Wiles proves that any equation of the form {{math|1=y2 {{=}} x(x − an)(x + bn)}} does have a modular form. Any non-trivial solution to {{math|1=xp + yp {{=}} zp}} (with {{math|1=p}} an odd prime) would therefore create a contradiction, which in turn proves that no non-trivial solutions exist.[11] In other words, any solution that could contradict Fermat's Last Theorem could also be used to contradict the Modularity Theorem. So if the modularity theorem were found to be true, then it would follow that no contradiction to Fermat's Last Theorem could exist either. As described above, the discovery of this equivalent statement was crucial to the eventual solution of Fermat's Last Theorem, as it provided a means by which it could be 'attacked' for all numbers at once. Mathematical historyPythagoras and DiophantusPythagorean triples{{Main|Pythagorean triple}}In ancient times it was known that a triangle whose sides were in the ratio 3:4:5 would have a right angle as one of its angles. This was used in construction and later in early geometry. It was also known to be one example of a general rule that any triangle where the length of two sides, each squared and then added together {{nowrap|1=(32 + 42 = 9 + 16 = 25)}}, equals the square of the length of the third side {{nowrap|1=(52 = 25)}}, would also be a right angle triangle. This is now known as the Pythagorean theorem, and a triple of numbers that meets this condition is called a Pythagorean triple – both are named after the ancient Greek Pythagoras. Examples include (3, 4, 5) and (5, 12, 13). There are infinitely many such triples,[12] and methods for generating such triples have been studied in many cultures, beginning with the Babylonians[13] and later ancient Greek, Chinese, and Indian mathematicians.[1] Mathematically, the definition of a Pythagorean triple is a set of three integers (a, b, c) that satisfy the equation[14] Diophantine equations{{Main|Diophantine equation}}Fermat's equation, xn + yn = zn with positive integer solutions, is an example of a Diophantine equation,[15] named for the 3rd-century Alexandrian mathematician, Diophantus, who studied them and developed methods for the solution of some kinds of Diophantine equations. A typical Diophantine problem is to find two integers x and y such that their sum, and the sum of their squares, equal two given numbers A and B, respectively: Diophantus's major work is the Arithmetica, of which only a portion has survived.[16] Fermat's conjecture of his Last Theorem was inspired while reading a new edition of the Arithmetica,[17] that was translated into Latin and published in 1621 by Claude Bachet.[18] Diophantine equations have been studied for thousands of years. For example, the solutions to the quadratic Diophantine equation x2 + y2 = z2 are given by the Pythagorean triples, originally solved by the Babylonians (c. 1800 BC).[19] Solutions to linear Diophantine equations, such as 26x + 65y = 13, may be found using the Euclidean algorithm (c. 5th century BC).[20] Many Diophantine equations have a form similar to the equation of Fermat's Last Theorem from the point of view of algebra, in that they have no cross terms mixing two letters, without sharing its particular properties. For example, it is known that there are infinitely many positive integers x, y, and z such that xn + yn = zm where n and m are relatively prime natural numbers.[21] Fermat's conjectureProblem II.8 of the Arithmetica asks how a given square number is split into two other squares; in other words, for a given rational number k, find rational numbers u and v such that k2 = u2 + v2. Diophantus shows how to solve this sum-of-squares problem for k = 4 (the solutions being u = 16/5 and v = 12/5).[22] Around 1637, Fermat wrote his Last Theorem in the margin of his copy of the Arithmetica next to Diophantus's sum-of-squares problem:[23]
After Fermat’s death in 1665, his son Clément-Samuel Fermat produced a new edition of the book (1670) augmented with his father’s comments.[26] Although not actually a theorem at the time (meaning a mathematical statement for which proof exists), the margin note became known over time as Fermat’s Last Theorem,[27] as it was the last of Fermat’s asserted theorems to remain unproved.[28] It is not known whether Fermat had actually found a valid proof for all exponents n, but it appears unlikely. Only one related proof by him has survived, namely for the case n = 4, as described in the section Proofs for specific exponents. While Fermat posed the cases of n = 4 and of n = 3 as challenges to his mathematical correspondents, such as Marin Mersenne, Blaise Pascal, and John Wallis,[29] he never posed the general case.[30] Moreover, in the last thirty years of his life, Fermat never again wrote of his "truly marvelous proof" of the general case, and never published it. Van der Poorten[31] suggests that while the absence of a proof is insignificant, the lack of challenges means Fermat realised he did not have a proof; he quotes Weil[32] as saying Fermat must have briefly deluded himself with an irretrievable idea. The techniques Fermat might have used in such a "marvelous proof" are unknown. Taylor and Wiles's proof relies on 20th-century techniques.[33] Fermat's proof would have had to be elementary by comparison, given the mathematical knowledge of his time. While Harvey Friedman's grand conjecture implies that any provable theorem (including Fermat's last theorem) can be proved using only 'elementary function arithmetic', such a proof need be ‘elementary’ only in a technical sense and could involve millions of steps, and thus be far too long to have been Fermat’s proof. Proofs for specific exponents{{Main|Proof of Fermat's Last Theorem for specific exponents}}Exponent = 4Only one relevant proof by Fermat has survived, in which he uses the technique of infinite descent to show that the area of a right triangle with integer sides can never equal the square of an integer.[34][35] His proof is equivalent to demonstrating that the equation has no primitive solutions in integers (no pairwise coprime solutions). In turn, this proves Fermat's Last Theorem for the case n = 4, since the equation a4 + b4 = c4 can be written as a4 + b4 = (c2)2. Alternative proofs of the case n = 4 were developed later[36] by Frénicle de Bessy (1676),[37] Leonhard Euler (1738),[38] Kausler (1802),[43] Peter Barlow (1811),[39] Adrien-Marie Legendre (1830),[45] Schopis (1825),[40] Olry Terquem (1846),[41] Joseph Bertrand (1851),[42] Victor Lebesgue (1853, 1859, 1862),[43] Théophile Pépin (1883),[44] Tafelmacher (1893),[45] David Hilbert (1897),[46] Bendz (1901),[47] Gambioli (1901),[54] Leopold Kronecker (1901),[48] Bang (1905),[49] Sommer (1907),[50] Bottari (1908),[51] Karel Rychlík (1910),[59] Nutzhorn (1912),[52] Robert Carmichael (1913),[53] Hancock (1931),[54] Vrǎnceanu (1966),[55], Grant and Perella (1999),[56] Barbara (2007),[57] and Dolan (2011).[58] Other exponentsAfter Fermat proved the special case n = 4, the general proof for all n required only that the theorem be established for all odd prime exponents.[59] In other words, it was necessary to prove only that the equation an + bn = cn has no integer solutions (a, b, c) when n is an odd prime number. This follows because a solution (a, b, c) for a given n is equivalent to a solution for all the factors of n. For illustration, let n be factored into d and e, n = de. The general equation an + bn = cn implies that (ad, bd, cd) is a solution for the exponent e (ad)e + (bd)e = (cd)e. Thus, to prove that Fermat's equation has no solutions for n > 2, it would suffice to prove that it has no solutions for at least one prime factor of every n. Each integer n > 2 is divisible by 4 or by an odd prime number (or both). Therefore, Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved for all n if it could be proved for n = 4 and for all odd primes p. In the two centuries following its conjecture (1637–1839), Fermat's Last Theorem was proved for three odd prime exponents p = 3, 5 and 7. The case p = 3 was first stated by Abu-Mahmud Khojandi (10th century), but his attempted proof of the theorem was incorrect.[60] In 1770, Leonhard Euler gave a proof of p = 3,[61] but his proof by infinite descent[62] contained a major gap.[63] However, since Euler himself had proved the lemma necessary to complete the proof in other work, he is generally credited with the first proof.[64] Independent proofs were published[65] by Kausler (1802),[66] Legendre (1823, 1830),[67][68] Calzolari (1855),[69] Gabriel Lamé (1865),[70] Peter Guthrie Tait (1872),[71] Günther (1878),[72]{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} Gambioli (1901),[73] Krey (1909),[74]{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} Rychlík (1910),[75] Stockhaus (1910),[76] Carmichael (1915),[77] Johannes van der Corput (1915),[78] Axel Thue (1917),[79]{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} and Duarte (1944).[80] The case p = 5 was proved[81] independently by Legendre and Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet around 1825.[82] Alternative proofs were developed[83] by Carl Friedrich Gauss (1875, posthumous),[84] Lebesgue (1843),[85] Lamé (1847),[86] Gambioli (1901),[73][87] Werebrusow (1905),[88]{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} Rychlík (1910),[89]{{dubious|date=October 2017|reason=it is unlikely that this article was published in the Bohemian language}}{{full citation needed|date=October 2017|reason=what is unabbreviated journal name?}} van der Corput (1915),[78] and Guy Terjanian (1987).[90] The case p = 7 was proved[91] by Lamé in 1839.[92] His rather complicated proof was simplified in 1840 by Lebesgue,[93] and still simpler proofs[94] were published by Angelo Genocchi in 1864, 1874 and 1876.[95] Alternative proofs were developed by Théophile Pépin (1876)[96] and Edmond Maillet (1897).[97] Fermat's Last Theorem was also proved for the exponents n = 6, 10, and 14. Proofs for n = 6 were published by Kausler,[66] Thue,[98] Tafelmacher,[99] Lind,[100] Kapferer,[101] Swift,[102] and Breusch.[103] Similarly, Dirichlet[104] and Terjanian[105] each proved the case n = 14, while Kapferer[101] and Breusch[103] each proved the case n = 10. Strictly speaking, these proofs are unnecessary, since these cases follow from the proofs for n = 3, 5, and 7, respectively. Nevertheless, the reasoning of these even-exponent proofs differs from their odd-exponent counterparts. Dirichlet's proof for n = 14 was published in 1832, before Lamé's 1839 proof for n = 7.[106] All proofs for specific exponents used Fermat's technique of infinite descent,{{citation needed|reason=this assertion requires a thorough review of all the existing literature, or a reliable source making the assertion|date=January 2015}} either in its original form, or in the form of descent on elliptic curves or abelian varieties. The details and auxiliary arguments, however, were often ad hoc and tied to the individual exponent under consideration.[107] Since they became ever more complicated as p increased, it seemed unlikely that the general case of Fermat's Last Theorem could be proved by building upon the proofs for individual exponents.[107] Although some general results on Fermat's Last Theorem were published in the early 19th century by Niels Henrik Abel and Peter Barlow,[108][109] the first significant work on the general theorem was done by Sophie Germain.[110] Early modern breakthroughsSophie GermainIn the early 19th century, Sophie Germain developed several novel approaches to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all exponents.[111] First, she defined a set of auxiliary primes θ constructed from the prime exponent p by the equation {{math|θ {{=}} 2hp + 1}}, where h is any integer not divisible by three. She showed that, if no integers raised to the pth power were adjacent modulo θ (the non-consecutivity condition), then θ must divide the product xyz. Her goal was to use mathematical induction to prove that, for any given p, infinitely many auxiliary primes θ satisfied the non-consecutivity condition and thus divided xyz; since the product xyz can have at most a finite number of prime factors, such a proof would have established Fermat's Last Theorem. Although she developed many techniques for establishing the non-consecutivity condition, she did not succeed in her strategic goal. She also worked to set lower limits on the size of solutions to Fermat's equation for a given exponent p, a modified version of which was published by Adrien-Marie Legendre. As a byproduct of this latter work, she proved Sophie Germain's theorem, which verified the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem (namely, the case in which p does not divide xyz) for every odd prime exponent less than 270,[111][112] and for all primes p such that at least one of 2p+1, 4p+1, 8p+1, 10p+1, 14p+1 and 16p+1 is prime (specially, the primes p such that 2p+1 is prime are called Sophie Germain primes). Germain tried unsuccessfully to prove the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem for all even exponents, specifically for {{math|n {{=}} 2p}}, which was proved by Guy Terjanian in 1977.[113] In 1985, Leonard Adleman, Roger Heath-Brown and Étienne Fouvry proved that the first case of Fermat's Last Theorem holds for infinitely many odd primes p.[114] Ernst Kummer and the theory of idealsIn 1847, Gabriel Lamé outlined a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem based on factoring the equation {{math|x{{sup|p}} + y{{sup|p}} {{=}} z{{sup|p}}}} in complex numbers, specifically the cyclotomic field based on the roots of the number 1. His proof failed, however, because it assumed incorrectly that such complex numbers can be factored uniquely into primes, similar to integers. This gap was pointed out immediately by Joseph Liouville, who later read a paper that demonstrated this failure of unique factorisation, written by Ernst Kummer. Kummer set himself the task of determining whether the cyclotomic field could be generalized to include new prime numbers such that unique factorisation was restored. He succeeded in that task by developing the ideal numbers. (Note: It is often stated that Kummer was led to his "ideal complex numbers" by his interest in Fermat's Last Theorem; there is even a story often told that Kummer, like Lamé, believed he had proven Fermat's Last Theorem until Lejeune Dirichlet told him his argument relied on unique factorization; but the story was first told by Kurt Hensel in 1910 and the evidence indicates it likely derives from a confusion by one of Hensel's sources. Harold Edwards says the belief that Kummer was mainly interested in Fermat's Last Theorem "is surely mistaken".[115] See the history of ideal numbers.) Using the general approach outlined by Lamé, Kummer proved both cases of Fermat's Last Theorem for all regular prime numbers. However, he could not prove the theorem for the exceptional primes (irregular primes) that conjecturally occur approximately 39% of the time; the only irregular primes below 270 are 37, 59, 67, 101, 103, 131, 149, 157, 233, 257 and 263. Mordell conjectureIn the 1920s, Louis Mordell posed a conjecture that implied that Fermat's equation has at most a finite number of nontrivial primitive integer solutions, if the exponent n is greater than two.[116] This conjecture was proved in 1983 by Gerd Faltings,[117] and is now known as Faltings's theorem. Computational studiesIn the latter half of the 20th century, computational methods were used to extend Kummer's approach to the irregular primes. In 1954, Harry Vandiver used a SWAC computer to prove Fermat's Last Theorem for all primes up to 2521.[118] By 1978, Samuel Wagstaff had extended this to all primes less than 125,000.[119] By 1993, Fermat's Last Theorem had been proved for all primes less than four million.[120] However despite these efforts and their results, no proof existed of Fermat's Last Theorem. Proofs of individual exponents by their nature could never prove the general case: even if all exponents were verified up to an extremely large number X, a higher exponent beyond X might still exist for which the claim was not true. (This had been the case with some other past conjectures, and it could not be ruled out in this conjecture.)[121] Connection with elliptic curvesThe strategy that ultimately led to a successful proof of Fermat's Last Theorem arose from the "astounding"[122]{{rp|211}} Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture, proposed around 1955—which many mathematicians believed would be near to impossible to prove,[122]{{rp|223}} and was linked in the 1980s by Gerhard Frey, Jean-Pierre Serre and Ken Ribet to Fermat's equation. By accomplishing a partial proof of this conjecture in 1994, Andrew Wiles ultimately succeeded in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, as well as leading the way to a full proof by others of what is now the modularity theorem. Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture{{main|Modularity theorem}}Around 1955, Japanese mathematicians Goro Shimura and Yutaka Taniyama observed a possible link between two apparently completely distinct branches of mathematics, elliptic curves and modular forms. The resulting modularity theorem (at the time known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) states that every elliptic curve is modular, meaning that it can be associated with a unique modular form. The link was initially dismissed as unlikely or highly speculative, but was taken more seriously when number theorist André Weil found evidence supporting it, though not proving it; as a result the conjecture was often known as the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture. It became a part of the Langlands programme, a list of important conjectures needing proof or disproof.[122]{{rp|211–215}} Even after gaining serious attention, the conjecture was seen by contemporary mathematicians as extraordinarily difficult or perhaps inaccessible to proof.[122]{{rp|203–205, 223, 226}} For example, Wiles's doctoral supervisor John Coates states that it seemed "impossible to actually prove",[122]{{rp|226}} and Ken Ribet considered himself "one of the vast majority of people who believed [it] was completely inaccessible", adding that "Andrew Wiles was probably one of the few people on earth who had the audacity to dream that you can actually go and prove [it]."[122]{{rp|223}} Ribet's theorem for Frey curves{{main|Frey curve|Ribet's theorem}}In 1984, Gerhard Frey noted a link between Fermat's equation and the modularity theorem, then still a conjecture. If Fermat's equation had any solution (a, b, c) for exponent p > 2, then it could be shown that the semi-stable elliptic curve (now known as a Frey-Hellegouarch[123]) y2 = x (x − ap)(x + bp) would have such unusual properties that it was unlikely to be modular.[124] This would conflict with the modularity theorem, which asserted that all elliptic curves are modular. As such, Frey observed that a proof of the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture might also simultaneously prove Fermat's Last Theorem.[125] By contraposition, a disproof or refutation of Fermat's Last Theorem would disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture. In plain English, Frey had shown that, if this intuition about his equation was correct, then any set of 4 numbers (a, b, c, n) capable of disproving Fermat's Last Theorem, could also be used to disprove the Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture. Therefore if the latter were true, the former could not be disproven, and would also have to be true. Following this strategy, a proof of Fermat's Last Theorem required two steps. First, it was necessary to prove the modularity theorem – or at least to prove it for the types of elliptical curves that included Frey's equation (known as semistable elliptic curves). This was widely believed inaccessible to proof by contemporary mathematicians.[122]{{rp|203–205, 223, 226}} Second, it was necessary to show that Frey's intuition was correct: that if an elliptic curve were constructed in this way, using a set of numbers that were a solution of Fermat's equation, the resulting elliptic curve could not be modular. Frey showed that this was plausible but did not go as far as giving a full proof. The missing piece (the so-called "epsilon conjecture", now known as Ribet's theorem) was identified by Jean-Pierre Serre who also gave an almost-complete proof and the link suggested by Frey was finally proved in 1986 by Ken Ribet.[126] Following Frey, Serre and Ribet's work, this was where matters stood:
Wiles's general proof{{Main|Andrew Wiles|Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem}}Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture in 1986 accomplished the first of the two goals proposed by Frey. Upon hearing of Ribet's success, Andrew Wiles, an English mathematician with a childhood fascination with Fermat's Last Theorem, and who had worked on elliptic curves, decided to commit himself to accomplishing the second half: proving a special case of the modularity theorem (then known as the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture) for semistable elliptic curves.[127] Wiles worked on that task for six years in near-total secrecy, covering up his efforts by releasing prior work in small segments as separate papers and confiding only in his wife.[122]{{rp|229–230}} His initial study suggested proof by induction,[122]{{rp|230–232, 249–252}} and he based his initial work and first significant breakthrough on Galois theory[122]{{rp|251–253, 259}} before switching to an attempt to extend horizontal Iwasawa theory for the inductive argument around 1990–91 when it seemed that there was no existing approach adequate to the problem.[122]{{rp|258–259}} However, by the summer of 1991, Iwasawa theory also seemed to not be reaching the central issues in the problem.[122]{{rp|259–260}}[128] In response, he approached colleagues to seek out any hints of cutting edge research and new techniques, and discovered an Euler system recently developed by Victor Kolyvagin and Matthias Flach that seemed "tailor made" for the inductive part of his proof.[122]{{rp|260–261}} Wiles studied and extended this approach, which worked. Since his work relied extensively on this approach, which was new to mathematics and to Wiles, in January 1993 he asked his Princeton colleague, Nick Katz, to help him check his reasoning for subtle errors. Their conclusion at the time was that the techniques Wiles used seemed to work correctly.[122]{{rp|261–265}}[129] By mid-May 1993, Wiles felt able to tell his wife he thought he had solved the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem,[122]{{rp|265}} and by June he felt sufficiently confident to present his results in three lectures delivered on 21–23 June 1993 at the Isaac Newton Institute for Mathematical Sciences.[130] Specifically, Wiles presented his proof of the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture for semistable elliptic curves; together with Ribet's proof of the epsilon conjecture, this implied Fermat's Last Theorem. However, it became apparent during peer review that a critical point in the proof was incorrect. It contained an error in a bound on the order of a particular group. The error was caught by several mathematicians refereeing Wiles's manuscript including Katz (in his role as reviewer),[131] who alerted Wiles on 23 August 1993.[132] The error would not have rendered his work worthless – each part of Wiles's work was highly significant and innovative by itself, as were the many developments and techniques he had created in the course of his work, and only one part was affected.[122]{{rp|289, 296–297}} However without this part proved, there was no actual proof of Fermat's Last Theorem. Wiles spent almost a year trying to repair his proof, initially by himself and then in collaboration with his former student Richard Taylor, without success.[133][134][135] By the end of 1993, rumours had spread that under scrutiny, Wiles's proof had failed, but how seriously was not known. Mathematicians were beginning to pressure Wiles to disclose his work whether or not complete, so that the wider community could explore and use whatever he had managed to accomplish. But instead of being fixed, the problem, which had originally seemed minor, now seemed very significant, far more serious, and less easy to resolve.[136] Wiles states that on the morning of 19 September 1994, he was on the verge of giving up and was almost resigned to accepting that he had failed, and to publishing his work so that others could build on it and find the error. He adds that he was having a final look to try and understand the fundamental reasons for why his approach could not be made to work, when he had a sudden insight – that the specific reason why the Kolyvagin–Flach approach would not work directly also meant that his original attempts using Iwasawa theory could be made to work, if he strengthened it using his experience gained from the Kolyvagin–Flach approach. Fixing one approach with tools from the other approach would resolve the issue for all the cases that were not already proven by his refereed paper.[133][137] He described later that Iwasawa theory and the Kolyvagin–Flach approach were each inadequate on their own, but together they could be made powerful enough to overcome this final hurdle.[133] "I was sitting at my desk examining the Kolyvagin–Flach method. It wasn't that I believed I could make it work, but I thought that at least I could explain why it didn’t work. Suddenly I had this incredible revelation. I realised that, the Kolyvagin–Flach method wasn't working, but it was all I needed to make my original Iwasawa theory work from three years earlier. So out of the ashes of Kolyvagin–Flach seemed to rise the true answer to the problem. It was so indescribably beautiful; it was so simple and so elegant. I couldn't understand how I'd missed it and I just stared at it in disbelief for twenty minutes. Then during the day I walked around the department, and I'd keep coming back to my desk looking to see if it was still there. It was still there. I couldn't contain myself, I was so excited. It was the most important moment of my working life. Nothing I ever do again will mean as much." — Andrew Wiles, as quoted by Simon Singh[138] On 24 October 1994, Wiles submitted two manuscripts, "Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem"[139] and "Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras",[140] the second of which was co-authored with Taylor and proved that certain conditions were met that were needed to justify the corrected step in the main paper. The two papers were vetted and published as the entirety of the May 1995 issue of the Annals of Mathematics. These papers established the modularity theorem for semistable elliptic curves, the last step in proving Fermat's Last Theorem, 358 years after it was conjectured. Subsequent developmentsThe full Taniyama–Shimura–Weil conjecture was finally proved by {{harvtxt|Diamond|1996}}, {{harvtxt|Conrad|Diamond|Taylor|1999}}, and {{harvtxt|Breuil|Conrad|Diamond|Taylor|2001}} who, building on Wiles's work, incrementally chipped away at the remaining cases until the full result was proved.[141][142][143] The now fully proved conjecture became known as the modularity theorem. Several other theorems in number theory similar to Fermat's Last Theorem also follow from the same reasoning, using the modularity theorem. For example: no cube can be written as a sum of two coprime n-th powers, n ≥ 3. (The case n = 3 was already known by Euler.) Relationship to other problems and generalizationsFermat's Last Theorem considers solutions to the Fermat equation: {{math|1=an + bn = cn}} with positive integers {{math|a}}, {{math|b}}, and {{math|c}} and an integer {{math|n}} greater than 2. There are several generalizations of the Fermat equation to more general equations that allow the exponent {{math|n}} to be a negative integer or rational, or to consider three different exponents. Generalized Fermat equationThe generalized Fermat equation generalizes the statement of Fermat's last theorem by considering positive integer solutions a, b, c, m, n, k satisfying[144] {{NumBlk|::||{{EquationRef|1}}}} In particular, the exponents m, n, k need not be equal, whereas Fermat's last theorem considers the case {{math|1=m = n = k.}}The Beal conjecture, also known as the Mauldin conjecture[145] and the Tijdeman-Zagier conjecture,[146][147][148] states that there are no solutions to the generalized Fermat equation in positive integers a, b, c, m, n, k with a, b, and c being pairwise coprime and all of m, n, k being greater than 2.[149] The Fermat–Catalan conjecture generalizes Fermat's last theorem with the ideas of the Catalan conjecture.[150][151] The conjecture states that the generalized Fermat equation has only finitely many solutions (a,b,c,m,n,k) with distinct triplets of values (am, bn, ck) where a, b, c are positive coprime integers and m, n, k are positive integers satisfying {{NumBlk|::||{{EquationRef|2}}}} The statement is about the finiteness of the set of solutions because there are 10 known known solutions.[144] Inverse Fermat equationWhen we allow the exponent {{math|n}} to be the reciprocal of an integer, i.e. {{math|1=n = 1/m}} for some integer {{math|m}}, we have the inverse Fermat equation All solutions of this equation were computed by Hendrik Lenstra in 1992.[152] In the case in which the mth roots are required to be real and positive, all solutions are given by[153] for positive integers r, s, t with s and t coprime. Rational exponentsFor the Diophantine equation with n not equal to 1, Bennett, Glass, and Székely proved in 2004 for n > 2, that if n and m are coprime, then there are integer solutions if and only if 6 divides m, and , and are different complex 6th roots of the same real number.[154] Negative integer exponentsn = –1All primitive integer solutions (i.e., those with no prime factor common to all of a, b, and c) to the optic equation can be written as[155] for positive, coprime integers m, k. n = –2The case n = –2 also has an infinitude of solutions, and these have a geometric interpretation in terms of right triangles with integer sides and an integer altitude to the hypotenuse.[156][157] All primitive solutions to are given by for coprime integers u, v with v > u. The geometric interpretation is that a and b are the integer legs of a right triangle and d is the integer altitude to the hypotenuse. Then the hypotenuse itself is the integer so (a, b, c) is a Pythagorean triple. n < –2There are no solutions in integers for for integers n < –2. If there were, the equation could be multiplied through by to obtain , which is impossible by Fermat's Last Theorem. abc conjectureThe abc conjecture roughly states that for three positive integers, a, b and c (hence the name) that are coprime and satisfy a + b = c, then the radical d of abc is usually not much smaller than c. In particular, the abc conjecture in its most standard formulation implies Fermat's last theorem for n that are sufficiently large.[158] An effective version of the abc conjecture implies Fermat's last theorem outright.[159] Monetary prizesIn 1816, and again in 1850, the French Academy of Sciences offered a prize for a general proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.[160] In 1857, the Academy awarded 3,000 francs and a gold medal to Kummer for his research on ideal numbers, although he had not submitted an entry for the prize.[161] Another prize was offered in 1883 by the Academy of Brussels.[162] In 1908, the German industrialist and amateur mathematician Paul Wolfskehl bequeathed 100,000 gold marks—a large sum at the time—to the Göttingen Academy of Sciences to offer as a prize for a complete proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.[163] On 27 June 1908, the Academy published nine rules for awarding the prize. Among other things, these rules required that the proof be published in a peer-reviewed journal; the prize would not be awarded until two years after the publication; and that no prize would be given after 13 September 2007, roughly a century after the competition was begun.[164] Wiles collected the Wolfskehl prize money, then worth $50,000, on 27 June 1997.[165] In March 2016, Wiles was awarded the Norwegian government's Abel prize worth €600,000 for "his stunning proof of Fermat’s Last Theorem by way of the modularity conjecture for semistable elliptic curves, opening a new era in number theory."[166] Prior to Wiles's proof, thousands of incorrect proofs were submitted to the Wolfskehl committee, amounting to roughly 10 feet (3 meters) of correspondence.[167] In the first year alone (1907–1908), 621 attempted proofs were submitted, although by the 1970s, the rate of submission had decreased to roughly 3–4 attempted proofs per month. According to F. Schlichting, a Wolfskehl reviewer, most of the proofs were based on elementary methods taught in schools, and often submitted by "people with a technical education but a failed career".[168] In the words of mathematical historian Howard Eves, "Fermat's Last Theorem has the peculiar distinction of being the mathematical problem for which the greatest number of incorrect proofs have been published."[162] In popular culture{{Main|Fermat's Last Theorem in fiction}}In The Simpsons episode "The Wizard of Evergreen Terrace" Homer writes the equation on a blackboard, which appears to be a counterexample to Fermat's Last Theorem. The equation is incorrect but appears to be correct if tested on a calculator displaying 10 significant figures.[169] In "The Royale", a 1989 episode of the 24th-century-set TV series The Next Generation, Picard tells Commander Riker about his attempts to solve the theorem, "still unsolved" after 800 years. He concludes, "In our arrogance, we feel we are so advanced. And yet we cannot unravel a simple knot tied by a part-time French mathematician working alone without a computer."[170] (Andrew Wiles's insight leading to his breakthrough proof happened four months after the series ended.[171]) See also{{Portal|Mathematics}}
Footnotes1. ^1 Singh, pp. 18–20. 2. ^1 2 Abel prize 2016 – full citation 3. ^{{cite book|title=The Guinness Book of World Records|year=1995|section=Science and Technology|publisher=Guinness Publishing Ltd.}} 4. ^If the exponent "n" were not prime or 4, then it would be possible to write n either as a product of two smaller integers (n = P*Q) in which P is a prime number greater than 2, and then an = aP*Q = (aQ)P for each of a, b, and c—i.e., an equivalent solution would also have to exist for the prime power P that is smaller than n, as well; or else as n would be a power of 2 greater than four and writing n=4*Q, the same argument would hold. 5. ^Singh p. 144 quotes Wiles's reaction to this news: "I was electrified. I knew that moment that the course of my life was changing because this meant that to prove Fermat’s Last Theorem all I had to do was to prove the Taniyama–Shimura conjecture. It meant that my childhood dream was now a respectable thing to work on." 6. ^1 Singh p. 144 7. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.nature.com/news/fermat-s-last-theorem-earns-andrew-wiles-the-abel-prize-1.19552 |title=Fermat's last theorem earns Andrew Wiles the Abel Prize |publisher=Nature |date=15 March 2016 |accessdate=15 March 2016}} 8. ^[https://www.washingtonpost.com/world/europe/british-mathematician-sir-andrew-wiles-gets-abel-math-prize/2016/03/15/41146a7e-eaa9-11e5-a9ce-681055c7a05f_story.html British mathematician Sir Andrew Wiles gets Abel math prize – The Washington Post] 9. ^300-year-old math question solved, professor wins $700k – CNN.com 10. ^{{cite journal|last=Wiles|first=Andrew|authorlink=Andrew Wiles|year=1995|title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem|url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf|quotation=Frey's suggestion, in the notation of the following theorem, was to show that the (hypothetical) elliptic curve {{math|1=y2 {{=}} x(x + up)(x – vp)}} could not be modular.|journal=Annals of Mathematics|volume=141|issue=3|page=448|oclc=37032255|doi=10.2307/2118559|jstor=2118559}} 11. ^{{cite journal|last=Ribet|first=Ken|authorlink=Ken Ribet|title=On modular representations of Gal({{overline|Q}}/Q) arising from modular forms|journal=Inventiones Mathematicae|volume=100|year=1990|issue=2|page=432|doi=10.1007/BF01231195|mr=1047143|url=http://math.berkeley.edu/~ribet/Articles/invent_100.pdf|format=PDF|bibcode=1990InMat.100..431R}} 12. ^{{cite book | author = Stillwell J | year = 2003 | title = Elements of Number Theory | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=LiAlZO2ntKAC&pg=PA110 | publisher = Springer-Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 0-387-95587-9 | pages = 110–112 | accessdate = 2016-03-17}} 13. ^Aczel, pp. 13–15 14. ^Stark, pp. 151–155. 15. ^Stark, pp. 145–146. 16. ^Singh, pp. 50–51. 17. ^Stark, p. 145. 18. ^Aczel, pp. 44–45; Singh, pp. 56–58. 19. ^Aczel, pp. 14–15. 20. ^Stark, pp. 44–47. 21. ^For example, 22. ^Friberg, pp. 333–334. 23. ^Dickson, p. 731; Singh, pp. 60–62; Aczel, p. 9. 24. ^T. Heath, Diophantus of Alexandria Second Edition, Cambridge University Press, 1910, reprinted by Dover, NY, 1964, pp. 144–145 25. ^Panchishkin, [https://books.google.com/books?id=wvK586IxaxwC&pg=PA341&dq=%22Cubum+autem+in+duos+cubos,+aut+quadratoquadratum%22&hl=en&ei=Jig_Tc2hCIH_8Aaf2LivCg&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=7&sqi=2&ved=0CEsQ6AEwBg#v=onepage&q=%22Cubum%20autem%20in%20duos%20cubos%2C%20aut%20quadratoquadratum%22&f=false p. 341] 26. ^Singh, pp. 62–66. 27. ^Dickson, p. 731. 28. ^Singh, p. 67; Aczel, p. 10. 29. ^Ribenboim, pp. 13, 24. 30. ^van der Poorten, Notes and Remarks 1.2, p. 5. 31. ^van der Poorten, loc. cit. 32. ^{{cite book | author = André Weil | year = 1984 | title = Number Theory: An approach through history. From Hammurapi to Legendre | publisher = Birkhäuser | location = Basel, Switzerland | page = 104}} 33. ^{{cite av media|url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ua8K8HW2Qsg#t=47m|title=BBC Documentary|publisher=}} 34. ^{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's One Proof | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-one-proof.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}} 35. ^Dickson, pp. 615–616; Aczel, p. 44. 36. ^Ribenboim, pp. 15–24. 37. ^Frénicle de Bessy, Traité des Triangles Rectangles en Nombres, vol. I, 1676, Paris. Reprinted in Mém. Acad. Roy. Sci., 5, 1666–1699 (1729). 38. ^{{cite journal | author = Euler L | year = 1738 | title = Theorematum quorundam arithmeticorum demonstrationes | journal = Novi Commentarii academiae scientiarum Petropolitanae | volume = 10 | pages = 125–146}}. Reprinted Opera omnia, ser. I, "Commentationes Arithmeticae", vol. I, pp. 38–58, Leipzig:Teubner (1915). 39. ^{{cite book | author = Barlow P | year = 1811 | title = An Elementary Investigation of Theory of Numbers | location = St. Paul's Church-Yard, London | publisher = J. Johnson | pages = 144–145}} 40. ^{{cite book | author = Schopis | year = 1825 | title = Einige Sätze aus der unbestimmten Analytik | publisher = Programm | location = Gummbinnen}} 41. ^{{cite journal | author = Terquem O | year = 1846 | title = Théorèmes sur les puissances des nombres | journal = Nouvelles Annales de Mathématiques | volume = 5 | pages = 70–87}} 42. ^{{cite book | author = Bertrand J | year = 1851 | title = Traité Élémentaire d'Algèbre | publisher = Hachette | location = Paris | pages = 217–230, 395}} 43. ^{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1853 | title = Résolution des équations biquadratiques z2 = x4 ± 2my4, z2 = 2mx4 − y4, 2mz2 = x4 ± y4 | journal = Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées | volume = 18 | pages = 73–86}} {{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1859 | title = Exercices d'Analyse Numérique | publisher = Leiber et Faraguet | location = Paris | pages = 83–84, 89}} {{cite book | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1862 | title = Introduction à la Théorie des Nombres | publisher = Mallet-Bachelier | location = Paris | pages = 71–73}} 44. ^{{cite journal | author = Pepin T | year = 1883 | title = Étude sur l'équation indéterminée ax4 + by4 = cz2 | journal = Atti della Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei. Classe di Scienze Fisiche, Matematiche e Naturali. Rendiconti Lincei. Serie IX. Matematica e Applicazioni. | volume = 36 | pages = 34–70}} 45. ^{{cite journal | author = A. Tafelmacher | year = 1893 | title = Sobre la ecuación x4 + y4 = z4 | journal = Anales de la Universidad de Chile | volume = 84 | pages = 307–320 |doi=10.5354/0717-8883.1893.20645}} 46. ^{{cite journal | author = Hilbert D | year = 1897 | title = Die Theorie der algebraischen Zahlkörper | journal = Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung | volume = 4 | pages = 175–546}} Reprinted in 1965 in Gesammelte Abhandlungen, vol. I by New York:Chelsea. 47. ^{{cite thesis | author = Bendz TR | year = 1901 | title = Öfver diophantiska ekvationen xn' + yn = zn | publisher = Almqvist & Wiksells Boktrycken | location = Uppsala}} 48. ^{{cite book | author = Kronecker L | year = 1901 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie, vol. I | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig | pages = 35–38}} Reprinted by New York:Springer-Verlag in 1978. 49. ^{{cite journal | author = Bang A | year = 1905 | title = Nyt Bevis for at Ligningen x4 − y4 = z4, ikke kan have rationale Løsinger | journal = Nyt tidsskrift for matematik | volume = 16B | pages = 31–35 |jstor=24528323}} 50. ^{{cite book | author = Sommer J | year = 1907 | title = Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie | publisher = Teubner | location = Leipzig}} 51. ^{{cite journal | author = Bottari A | year = 1908 | title = Soluzione intere dell'equazione pitagorica e applicazione alla dimostrazione di alcune teoremi della teoria dei numeri | journal = Periodico di Matematiche | volume = 23 | pages = 104–110}} 52. ^{{cite journal | author = Nutzhorn F | year = 1912 | title = Den ubestemte Ligning x4 + y4 = z4 | journal = Nyt tidsskrift for matematik | volume = 23B | pages = 33–38}} 53. ^{{cite journal | author = Carmichael RD | year = 1913 | title = On the impossibility of certain Diophantine equations and systems of equations | journal = American Mathematical Monthly | volume = 20 | pages = 213–221 | doi = 10.2307/2974106 | issue = 7 | publisher = Mathematical Association of America | jstor = 2974106}} 54. ^{{cite book | author = Hancock H | year = 1931 | title = Foundations of the Theory of Algebraic Numbers, vol. I | publisher = Macmillan | location = New York}} 55. ^{{cite journal | author = Vrǎnceanu G | year = 1966 | title = Asupra teorema lui Fermat pentru n=4 | journal = Gazeta Matematică Seria A | volume = 71 | pages = 334–335}} Reprinted in 1977 in Opera matematica, vol. 4, pp. 202–205, Bucureşti: Editura Academiei Republicii Socialiste România. 56. ^Grant, Mike, and Perella, Malcolm, "Descending to the irrational", Mathematical Gazette 83, July 1999, pp. 263–267. 57. ^Barbara, Roy, "Fermat's last theorem in the case n=4", Mathematical Gazette 91, July 2007, 260–262. 58. ^Dolan, Stan, "Fermat's method of descente infinie", Mathematical Gazette 95, July 2011, 269–271. 59. ^Ribenboim, pp. 1–2. 60. ^Dickson, p. 545. {{MacTutor|id=Al-Khujandi|title=Abu Mahmud Hamid ibn al-Khidr Al-Khujandi}} 61. ^Euler L (1770) Vollständige Anleitung zur Algebra, Roy. Acad. Sci., St. Petersburg. 62. ^{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 3 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/05/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n3.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}} 63. ^Ribenboim, pp. 24–25; Mordell, pp. 6–8; Edwards, pp. 39–40. 64. ^Aczel, p. 44; Edwards, pp. 40, 52–54. {{cite journal |author=J. J. Mačys |title=On Euler's hypothetical proof |journal=Mathematical Notes |year=2007 |volume=82 |issue=3–4 |pages=352–356 |url=http://www.springerlink.com/content/u46jj0nuk3678591/ |doi=10.1134/S0001434607090088 |mr=2364600}} 65. ^Ribenboim, pp. 33, 37–41. 66. ^1 2 {{cite journal | author = Kausler CF | year = 1802 | title = Nova demonstratio theorematis nec summam, nec differentiam duorum cuborum cubum esse posse | journal =Novi Acta Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae | volume = 13 | pages = 245–253}} 67. ^1 {{cite book | author = Legendre AM | year = 1830 | title = Théorie des Nombres (Volume II) | edition = 3rd | publisher = Firmin Didot Frères | location = Paris}} Reprinted in 1955 by A. Blanchard (Paris). 68. ^{{cite journal | author = Legendre AM | year = 1823 | title = Recherches sur quelques objets d'analyse indéterminée, et particulièrement sur le théorème de Fermat | journal = Mémoires de l'Académie royale des sciences | volume = 6 | pages = 1–60}} Reprinted in 1825 as the "Second Supplément" for a printing of the 2nd edition of Essai sur la Théorie des Nombres, Courcier (Paris). Also reprinted in 1909 in Sphinx-Oedipe, 4, 97–128. 69. ^{{cite book | author = Calzolari L | year = 1855 | title = Tentativo per dimostrare il teorema di Fermat sull'equazione indeterminata xn + yn = zn | publisher = Ferrara}} 70. ^{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1865 | title = Étude des binômes cubiques x3 ± y3 | journal = Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences | volume = 61 | pages = 921–924, 961–965}} 71. ^{{cite journal | author = Tait PG | year = 1872 | title = Mathematical Notes | journal = Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh | volume = 7 | page = 144 | doi=10.1017/s0370164600041857}} 72. ^{{cite journal | author = Günther S | year = 1878 | title = Über die unbestimmte Gleichung x3 + y3 = z3 | journal = Sitzungsberichte Böhm. Ges. Wiss. | pages = 112–120}} 73. ^1 2 {{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | year = 1901 | title = Memoria bibliographica sull'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Periodico di Matematiche | volume = 16 | pages = 145–192}} 74. ^{{cite journal | author = Krey H | year = 1909 | title = Neuer Beweis eines arithmetischen Satzes | journal = Math. Naturwiss. Blätter | volume = 6 | pages = 179–180}} 75. ^1 {{cite journal | author = Rychlik K | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for n = 4 and n = 3 (in Bohemian) | journal = Časopis pro pěstování matematiky a fysiky | volume = 39 | pages = 65–86}} 76. ^{{cite book | author = Stockhaus H | year = 1910 | title = Beitrag zum Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes | publisher = Brandstetter | location = Leipzig}} 77. ^{{cite book | author = Carmichael RD | year = 1915 | title = Diophantine Analysis | publisher = Wiley | location = New York}} 78. ^1 {{cite journal | author = van der Corput JG | year = 1915 | title = Quelques formes quadratiques et quelques équations indéterminées | journal = Nieuw Archief voor Wiskunde | volume = 11 | pages = 45–75}} 79. ^{{cite journal | author = Thue A | year = 1917 | title = Et bevis for at ligningen A3 + B3 = C3 er unmulig i hele tal fra nul forskjellige tal A, B og C | journal = Arch. Mat. Naturv. | volume = 34 | issue = 15}} Reprinted in Selected Mathematical Papers (1977), Oslo:Universitetsforlaget, pp. 555–559. 80. ^{{cite journal | author = Duarte FJ | year = 1944 | title = Sobre la ecuación x3 + y3 + z3 = 0 | journal = Boletín de la Academia de Ciencias Físicas, Matemáticas y Naturales (Caracas) | volume = 8 | pages = 971–979}} 81. ^{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 5 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2005/10/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n5_28.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}} 82. ^Ribenboim, p. 49; Mordell, p. 8–9; Aczel, p. 44; Singh, p. 106. 83. ^Ribenboim, pp. 55–57. 84. ^{{cite book | author = Gauss CF | year = 1875 | chapter = Neue Theorie der Zerlegung der Cuben | title = Zur Theorie der complexen Zahlen, Werke, vol. II | edition = 2nd | publisher = Königl. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen | pages = 387–391}} (Published posthumously) 85. ^{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1843 | title = Théorèmes nouveaux sur l'équation indéterminée x5 + y5 = az5 | journal = Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées | volume = 8 | pages = 49–70}} 86. ^{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1847 | title = Mémoire sur la résolution en nombres complexes de l'équation A5 + B5 + C5 = 0 | journal = Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées | volume = 12 | pages = 137–171}} 87. ^{{cite journal | author = Gambioli D | year = 1903{{ndash}}1904 | title = Intorno all'ultimo teorema di Fermat | journal = Il Pitagora | volume = 10 | pages = 11–13, 41–42}} 88. ^{{cite journal | author = Werebrusow AS | year = 1905 | title = On the equation x5 + y5 = Az5 (in Russian) | journal = Moskov. Math. Samml. | volume = 25 | pages = 466–473}} 89. ^{{cite journal | author = Rychlik K | year = 1910 | title = On Fermat's last theorem for n = 5 (in Bohemian) | journal = Časopis Pěst. Mat. | volume = 39 | pages = 185–195, 305–317}} 90. ^{{cite journal | author = Terjanian G | year = 1987 | title = Sur une question de V. A. Lebesgue | journal = Annales de l'Institut Fourier | volume = 37 | pages = 19–37 | doi=10.5802/aif.1096}} 91. ^Ribenboim, pp. 57–63; Mordell, p. 8; Aczel, p. 44; Singh, p. 106. 92. ^{{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1839 | title = Mémoire sur le dernier théorème de Fermat | journal = Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences | volume = 9 | pages = 45–46}} {{cite journal | author = Lamé G | year = 1840 | title = Mémoire d'analyse indéterminée démontrant que l'équation x7 + y7 = z7 est impossible en nombres entiers | journal = Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées | volume = 5 | pages = 195–211}} 93. ^{{cite journal | author = Lebesgue VA | year = 1840 | title = Démonstration de l'impossibilité de résoudre l'équation x7 + y7 + z7 = 0 en nombres entiers | journal = Journal de Mathématiques Pures et Appliquées | volume = 5 | pages = 276–279, 348–349}} 94. ^{{cite web | author = Freeman L | title = Fermat's Last Theorem: Proof for n = 7 | url = http://fermatslasttheorem.blogspot.com/2006/01/fermats-last-theorem-proof-for-n7.html | accessdate = 23 May 2009}} 95. ^{{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1864 | title = Intorno all'equazioni x7 + y7 + z7 = 0 | journal = Annali di Matematica Pura ed Applicata | volume = 6 | pages = 287–288 | doi=10.1007/bf03198884}} {{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1874 | title = Sur l'impossibilité de quelques égalités doubles | journal = Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences | volume = 78 | pages = 433–436}} {{cite journal | author = Genocchi A | year = 1876 | title = Généralisation du théorème de Lamé sur l'impossibilité de l'équation x7 + y7 + z7 = 0 | journal = Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences | volume = 82 | pages = 910–913}} 96. ^{{cite journal | author = Pepin T | year = 1876 | title = Impossibilité de l'équation x7 + y7 + z7 = 0 | journal = Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des Sciences | volume = 82 | pages = 676–679, 743–747}} 97. ^{{cite journal | author = Maillet E | year = 1897 | title = Sur l'équation indéterminée axλt + byλt = czλt | journal = Association française pour l'avancement des sciences, St. Etienne, Compte Rendu de la 26me Session, deuxième partie | volume = 26 | pages = 156–168 |url=http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k201187c/f159.image}} 98. ^{{cite journal | author = Thue A | year = 1896 | title = Über die Auflösbarkeit einiger unbestimmter Gleichungen | journal = Det Kongelige Norske Videnskabers Selskabs Skrifter | volume = 7}} Reprinted in Selected Mathematical Papers, pp. 19–30, Oslo:Universitetsforlaget (1977). 99. ^{{cite journal | author = Tafelmacher WLA | year = 1897 | title = La ecuación x3 + y3 = z2: Una demonstración nueva del teorema de fermat para el caso de las sestas potencias | journal = Anales de la Universidad de Chile | volume = 97 | pages = 63–80}} 100. ^{{cite journal | author = Lind B | year = 1909 | title = Einige zahlentheoretische Sätze | journal = Archiv der Mathematik und Physik | volume = 15 | pages = 368–369}} 101. ^1 {{cite journal | author = Kapferer H | year = 1913 | title = Beweis des Fermatschen Satzes für die Exponenten 6 und 10 | journal = Archiv der Mathematik und Physik | volume = 21 | pages = 143–146}} 102. ^{{cite journal | author = Swift E | year = 1914 | title = Solution to Problem 206 | journal = American Mathematical Monthly | volume = 21 | pages = 238–239 | doi = 10.2307/2972379 }} 103. ^1 {{cite journal | doi = 10.2307/3029800 | author = Breusch R | authorlink = Robert Breusch | year = 1960 | title = A simple proof of Fermat's last theorem for n = 6, n = 10 | journal = Mathematics Magazine | volume = 33 | issue = 5 | pages = 279–281 | jstor = 3029800}} 104. ^{{cite journal | author = Dirichlet PGL | year = 1832 | title = Démonstration du théorème de Fermat pour le cas des 14e puissances | journal = Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik | volume = 9 | pages = 390–393}} Reprinted in Werke, vol. I, pp. 189–194, Berlin: G. Reimer (1889); reprinted New York:Chelsea (1969). 105. ^{{cite journal | author = Terjanian G | year = 1974 | title= L'équation x14 + y14 = z14 en nombres entiers | journal = Bulletin des Sciences Mathématiques (sér. 2) | volume = 98 | pages = 91–95}} 106. ^Edwards, pp. 73–74. 107. ^1 Edwards, p. 74. 108. ^Dickson, p. 733. 109. ^{{cite book | author = Ribenboim P | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | pages = 51–54}} 110. ^Singh, pp. 97–109. 111. ^1 {{cite web |vauthors=Laubenbacher R, Pengelley D | year = 2007 | title = Voici ce que j'ai trouvé: Sophie Germain's grand plan to prove Fermat's Last Theorem | url = http://www.math.nmsu.edu/%7Edavidp/germain.pdf | accessdate = 19 May 2009}} 112. ^Aczel, p. 57. 113. ^{{cite journal|last=Terjanian|first=G.|year=1977|title=Sur l'équation x2p + y2p = z2p |journal=Comptes Rendus de l'Académie des Sciences, Série A-B|volume=285|pages=973–975}} 114. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Adleman LM, Heath-Brown DR |date=June 1985 |title = The first case of Fermat's last theorem | journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 79 | issue = 2 |pages = 409–416 | publisher = Springer | location = Berlin | doi=10.1007/BF01388981 | bibcode=1985InMat..79..409A}} 115. ^Harold M. Edwards, Fermat's Last Theorem. A genetic introduction to number theory. Graduate Texts in Mathematics vol. 50, Springer-Verlag, NY, 1977, p. 79 116. ^Aczel, pp. 84–88; Singh, pp. 232–234. 117. ^{{cite journal | author = Faltings G | year = 1983 | title = Endlichkeitssätze für abelsche Varietäten über Zahlkörpern |journal = Inventiones Mathematicae | volume = 73 | issue = 3 |pages = 349–366 |doi=10.1007/BF01388432|bibcode = 1983InMat..73..349F }} 118. ^{{cite book | author = Ribenboim P | year = 1979 | title = 13 Lectures on Fermat's Last Theorem | publisher = Springer Verlag | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-387-90432-0 | page = 202}} 119. ^{{cite journal | author = Wagstaff SS, Jr. | year = 1978 | title = The irregular primes to 125000 | journal = Mathematics of Computation | volume = 32 | pages = 583–591 | doi = 10.2307/2006167 | issue = 142 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | jstor = 2006167}} (PDF) {{webarchive |url=https://www.webcitation.org/5vcghCvCT?url=http://www.ams.org/journals/mcom/1978-32-142/S0025-5718-1978-0491465-4/S0025-5718-1978-0491465-4.pdf |date=10 January 2011 }} 120. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Buhler J, Crandell R, Ernvall R, Metsänkylä T | year = 1993 | title = Irregular primes and cyclotomic invariants to four million | journal = Mathematics of Computation | volume = 61 | pages = 151–153 | doi = 10.2307/2152942 | issue = 203 | publisher = American Mathematical Society | jstor = 2152942}} 121. ^{{Cite web|url=https://mathoverflow.net/questions/15444/examples-of-eventual-counterexamples/28196#28196|title=Examples of eventual counterexamples, answer by J.D. Hamkins|last=Hamkins|first=Joel David|date=June 15, 2010|website=mathoverflow.net|access-date=June 15, 2017}} 122. ^1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 Fermat's Last Theorem, Simon Singh, 1997, {{isbn|1-85702-521-0}} 123. ^This elliptic curve was first suggested in the 1960s by {{Interlanguage link multi|Yves Hellegouarch|de}}, but he did not call attention to its non-modularity. For more details, see {{Cite book | last=Hellegouarch | first=Yves | title=Invitation to the Mathematics of Fermat-Wiles | publisher=Academic Press | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-12-339251-0 }} 124. ^{{cite journal | author = Frey G | year = 1986 |title = Links between stable elliptic curves and certain diophantine equations | journal = Annales Universitatis Saraviensis. Series Mathematicae. | volume = 1 | pages = 1–40}} 125. ^Singh, pp. 194–198; Aczel, pp. 109–114. 126. ^{{cite journal|last=Ribet|first=Ken|authorlink=Ken Ribet|title=On modular representations of Gal({{overline|Q}}/Q) arising from modular forms|journal=Inventiones Mathematicae|volume=100|year=1990|issue=2|pages=431–476|doi=10.1007/BF01231195|mr=1047143|url=http://math.berkeley.edu/~ribet/Articles/invent_100.pdf|format=PDF|bibcode=1990InMat.100..431R}} 127. ^Singh, p. 205; Aczel, pp. 117–118. 128. ^Singh, pp. 237–238; Aczel, pp. 121–122. 129. ^Singh, pp. 239–243; Aczel, pp. 122–125. 130. ^Singh, pp. 244–253; Aczel, pp. 1–4, 126–128. 131. ^Aczel, pp. 128–130. 132. ^Singh, p. 257. 133. ^1 2 Singh, pp. 269–277. 134. ^[https://www.nytimes.com/1994/06/28/science/a-year-later-snag-persists-in-math-proof.html A Year Later, Snag Persists In Math Proof] 28 June 1994 135. ^[https://www.nytimes.com/1994/07/03/weekinreview/june-26-july-2-a-year-later-fermat-s-puzzle-is-still-not-quite-qed.html 26 June – 2 July; A Year Later Fermat's Puzzle Is Still Not Quite Q.E.D.] 3 July 1994 136. ^Singh, pp. 175–185. 137. ^Aczel, pp. 132–134. 138. ^Singh p. 186–187 (text condensed). 139. ^{{cite journal|last=Wiles|first=Andrew|authorlink=Andrew Wiles|year=1995|title=Modular elliptic curves and Fermat's Last Theorem|url=http://math.stanford.edu/~lekheng/flt/wiles.pdf|journal=Annals of Mathematics|volume=141|issue=3|pages=443–551|oclc=37032255|doi=10.2307/2118559|jstor=2118559}} 140. ^{{cite journal|author=Taylor R, Wiles A |year=1995 |journal=Annals of Mathematics |title=Ring theoretic properties of certain Hecke algebras |volume=141 |issue=3 |pages=553–572 |oclc=37032255 |url=http://www.math.harvard.edu/~rtaylor/hecke.ps |doi=10.2307/2118560 |jstor=2118560 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20011127181043/http://www.math.harvard.edu/~rtaylor/hecke.ps |archivedate=27 November 2001 }} 141. ^{{cite journal | last1=Diamond | first1=Fred | title=On deformation rings and Hecke rings | doi=10.2307/2118586 | mr=1405946 | year=1996 | journal=Annals of Mathematics | series = Second Series | issn=0003-486X | volume=144 | issue=1 | pages=137–166 | ref=harv}} 142. ^{{cite journal | last1=Conrad | first1=Brian | last2=Diamond | first2=Fred | last3=Taylor | first3=Richard | title=Modularity of certain potentially Barsotti-Tate Galois representations | doi=10.1090/S0894-0347-99-00287-8 | mr=1639612 | year=1999 | journal=Journal of the American Mathematical Society | issn=0894-0347 | volume=12 | issue=2 | pages=521–567 | ref=harv}} 143. ^{{cite journal | last1=Breuil | first1=Christophe | last2=Conrad | first2=Brian | last3=Diamond | first3=Fred | last4=Taylor | first4=Richard | title=On the modularity of elliptic curves over Q: wild 3-adic exercises | doi=10.1090/S0894-0347-01-00370-8 | mr=1839918 | year=2001 | journal=Journal of the American Mathematical Society | issn=0894-0347 | volume=14 | issue=4 | pages=843–939 | ref=harv}} 144. ^1 {{cite book|title=The Princeton Companion to Mathematics|last1=Barrow-Green|first1=June|last2=Leader|first2=Imre|last3=Gowers|first3=Timothy|pages=361-362|year=2008|publisher=Princeton University Press}} 145. ^{{cite web| url = http://www.primepuzzles.net/puzzles/puzz_559.htm | title = Mauldin / Tijdeman-Zagier Conjecture | publisher = Prime Puzzles | access-date = 1 October 2016}} 146. ^{{cite journal|last=Elkies| first = Noam D. | title=The ABC's of Number Theory | journal = The Harvard College Mathematics Review | year=2007 | volume=1 | issue = 1 | url=http://dash.harvard.edu/bitstream/handle/1/2793857/Elkies%20-%20ABCs%20of%20Number%20Theory.pdf?sequence=2}} 147. ^{{cite journal|journal=Moscow Mathematics|volume=4|year=2004|title=Open Diophantine Problems|pages=245–305|author=Michel Waldschmidt|doi=10.17323/1609-4514-2004-4-1-245-305}} 148. ^{{cite book |title=Prime Numbers: A Computational Perspective |last1=Crandall |first1=Richard |last2=Pomerance |first2=Carl |year=2000 |isbn=978-0387-25282-7 |publisher=Springer |page=417}} 149. ^{{cite web| url=http://www.ams.org/profession/prizes-awards/ams-supported/beal-conjecture | title=Beal Conjecture | publisher=American Mathematical Society | access-date=21 August 2016}} 150. ^{{cite journal|title=A new generalization of Fermat's Last Theorem|last1=Cai|first1=Tianxin|last2=Chen|first2=Deyi|last3=Zhang|first3=Yong|journal=Journal of Number Theory|volume=149|year=2015|pages=33-45}} 151. ^{{cite journal|title=A Cyclotomic Investigation of the Catalan -- Fermat Conjecture|last=Mihailescu|first=Preda|journal=Mathematica Gottingensis|year=2007}} 152. ^{{cite journal | author = Lenstra Jr. H.W. | authorlink = Hendrik Lenstra | year = 1992 | title = On the inverse Fermat equation | url = | journal = Discrete Mathematics | volume = 106–107 | issue = | pages = 329–331 | doi = 10.1016/0012-365x(92)90561-s }} 153. ^{{cite journal | author = Newman M | year = 1981 | title = A radical diophantine equation | doi = 10.1016/0022-314x(81)90040-8 | journal = Journal of Number Theory | volume = 13 | issue = | pages = 495–498 }} 154. ^{{cite journal | last1 = Bennett | first1 = Curtis D. | last2 = Glass | first2 = A. M. W. | last3 = Székely | first3 = Gábor J. | doi = 10.2307/4145241 | issue = 4 | journal = American Mathematical Monthly | mr = 2057186 | pages = 322–329 | title = Fermat's last theorem for rational exponents | volume = 111 | year = 2004}} 155. ^Dickson, pp. 688–691 156. ^{{cite journal|last=Voles|first=Roger|title=Integer solutions of a−2 + b−2 = d−2|journal=Mathematical Gazette|volume=83|date=July 1999|pages=269–271}} 157. ^{{cite journal|last=Richinick|first=Jennifer|title=The upside-down Pythagorean Theorem|journal=Mathematical Gazette|volume=92|date=July 2008|pages=313–317}} 158. ^{{cite book|title=Algebra|last=Lang|first=Serge|authorlink=Serge Lang|publisher=Springer-Verlag New York|series=Graduate Texts in Mathematics|volume=211|year=2002|page=196}} 159. ^{{cite journal | last1 = Granville | first1 = Andrew | last2 = Tucker | first2 = Thomas | year = 2002 | title = It's As Easy As abc | url = http://www.ams.org/notices/200210/fea-granville.pdf | format = PDF | journal = Notices of the AMS | volume = 49 | issue = 10| pages = 1224–1231 }} 160. ^Aczel, p. 69; Singh, p. 105. 161. ^Aczel, p. 69. 162. ^1 {{cite book | author = Koshy T | year = 2001 | title = Elementary number theory with applications | publisher = Academic Press | location = New York | isbn = 978-0-12-421171-1 | page = 544}} 163. ^Singh, pp. 120–125, 131–133, 295–296; Aczel, p. 70. 164. ^Singh, pp. 120–125. 165. ^Singh, p. 284 166. ^{{cite web| url = http://www.abelprize.no/c67107/binfil/download.php?tid=67059 | title =The Abel Prize citation 2016 | date = March 2016 | website = The Abel Prize | publisher = The Abel Prize Committee |format = PDF | access-date = 16 March 2016}} 167. ^Singh, p. 295. 168. ^Singh, pp. 295–296. 169. ^{{Cite book|title=The Simpsons and their Mathematical Secrets|first=Simon|last=Singh|isbn=978-1-4088-3530-2|year=2013|location=London|pages=35–36}} 170. ^{{cite news |author=Kevin Knudson |date=20 August 2015 |title=The Math Of Star Trek: How Trying To Solve Fermat's Last Theorem Revolutionized Mathematics |publisher=Forbes |url=https://www.forbes.com/sites/kevinknudson/2015/08/20/the-math-of-star-trek-how-trying-to-solve-fermats-last-theorem-revolutionized-mathematics/amp/}} 171. ^{{cite web|title=Are mathematicians finally satisfied with Andrew Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem? Why has this theorem been so difficult to prove?|url=http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/are-mathematicians-finall/|work=Scientific American|accessdate=16 March 2016|date=21 October 1999}} References{{Reflist}}Bibliography{{refbegin|30em}}
Further reading{{refbegin|30em}}
External links{{Wikibooks}}{{Wikiquote}}
7 : Fermat's Last Theorem|1637 in science|1637 introductions|Articles with inconsistent citation formats|Pythagorean theorem|Theorems in number theory|Conjectures that have been proved |
||
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。