请输入您要查询的百科知识:

 

词条 Kripke semantics
释义

  1. Semantics of modal logic

     Basic definitions   Correspondence and completeness    Common modal axiom schemata    Common modal systems   Canonical models  Finite model property  Multimodal logics 

  2. Semantics of intuitionistic logic

     Intuitionistic first-order logic  Kripke–Joyal semantics 

  3. Model constructions

  4. General frame semantics

  5. Computer science applications

  6. History and terminology

  7. See also

  8. Notes

  9. References

  10. External links

{{more footnotes|date=April 2013}}

Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André Joyal. It was first conceived for modal logics, and later adapted to intuitionistic logic and other non-classical systems. The development of Kripke semantics was a breakthrough in the theory of non-classical logics, because the model theory of such logics was almost non-existent before Kripke (algebraic semantics existed, but were considered 'syntax in disguise').

Semantics of modal logic

{{Main| Modal logic }}

The language of propositional modal logic consists of a countably infinite set of propositional variables, a set of truth-functional connectives (in this article and ), and the modal operator ("necessarily"). The modal operator ("possibly") is (classically) the dual of and may be defined in terms of necessity like so: ("possibly A" is defined as equivalent to "not necessarily not A").[1]

Basic definitions

A Kripke frame or modal frame is a pair , where W is a (possibly empty) set, and R is a binary relation on W. Elements

of W are called nodes or worlds, and R is known as the accessibility relation.[2]

A Kripke model is a triple , where

is a Kripke frame, and is a relation between

nodes of W and modal formulas, such that:

  • if and only if ,
  • if and only if or ,
  • if and only if for all such that .

We read as “w satisfies

A”, “A is satisfied in w”, or

w forces A”. The relation is called the

satisfaction relation, evaluation, or forcing relation.

The satisfaction relation is uniquely determined by its

value on propositional variables.

A formula A is valid in:

  • a model , if for all w ∈ W,
  • a frame , if it is valid in for all possible choices of ,
  • a class C of frames or models, if it is valid in every member of C.

We define Thm(C) to be the set of all formulas that are valid in

C. Conversely, if X is a set of formulas, let Mod(X) be the

class of all frames which validate every formula from X.

A modal logic (i.e., a set of formulas) L is sound with

respect to a class of frames C, if L ⊆ Thm(C). L is

complete wrt C if L ⊇ Thm(C).

Correspondence and completeness

Semantics is useful for investigating a logic (i.e. a derivation system) only if the semantic consequence relation reflects its syntactical counterpart, the syntactic consequence relation (derivability).[3] It is vital to know which modal logics are sound and complete with respect to a class of Kripke frames, and to determine also which class that is.

For any class C of Kripke frames, Thm(C) is a normal modal logic (in particular, theorems of the minimal normal modal logic, K, are valid in every Kripke model). However, the converse does not hold in general: while most of the modal systems studied are complete of classes of frames described by simple conditions,

Kripke incomplete normal modal logics do exist. A natural example of such a system is Japaridze's Polymodal Logic.

A normal modal logic L corresponds to a class of frames C, if C = Mod(L). In other words, C is the largest class of frames such that L is sound wrt C. It follows that L is Kripke complete if and only if it is complete of its corresponding class.

Consider the schema T : .

T is valid in any reflexive frame : if

, then

since w R w. On the other hand, a frame which

validates T has to be reflexive: fix w ∈ W, and

define satisfaction of a propositional variable p as follows:

if and only if w R u. Then

, thus

by T, which means w R w using the definition of

. T corresponds to the class of reflexive

Kripke frames.

It is often much easier to characterize the corresponding class of

L than to prove its completeness, thus correspondence serves as a

guide to completeness proofs. Correspondence is also used to show

incompleteness of modal logics: suppose

L1 ⊆ L2 are normal modal logics that

correspond to the same class of frames, but L1 does not

prove all theorems of L2. Then L1 is

Kripke incomplete. For example, the schema generates an incomplete logic, as it

corresponds to the same class of frames as GL (viz. transitive and

converse well-founded frames), but does not prove the GL-tautology .

Common modal axiom schemata

The following table lists common modal axioms together with their corresponding classes. The naming of the axioms often varies.

Name Axiom Frame condition
K N/A
T reflexive:
4 transitive:
dense:
D or serial:
B symmetric :
5 Euclidean:
GL R transitive, R−1 well-founded
Grz R reflexive and transitive, R−1Id well-founded
H
M (a complicated second-order property)
G convergent:
partial function:
function:
or empty:

Common modal systems

{{:Normal modal logic}}

Canonical models

For any normal modal logic, L, a Kripke model (called the canonical model) can be constructed that refutes precisely the non-theorems of

L, by an adaptation of the standard technique of using maximal consistent sets as models. Canonical Kripke models play a

role similar to the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra construction in algebraic

semantics.

A set of formulas is L-consistent if no contradiction can be derived from it using the theorems of L, and Modus Ponens. A maximal L-consistent set (an L-MCS

for short) is an L-consistent set that has no proper L-consistent superset.

The canonical model of L is a Kripke model

, where W is the set of all L-MCS,

and the relations R and are as follows:

if and only if for every formula , if then ,

if and only if .

The canonical model is a model of L, as every L-MCS contains

all theorems of L. By Zorn's lemma, each L-consistent set

is contained in an L-MCS, in particular every formula

unprovable in L has a counterexample in the canonical model.

The main application of canonical models are completeness proofs. Properties of the canonical model of K immediately imply completeness of K with respect to the class of all Kripke frames.

This argument does not work for arbitrary L, because there is no guarantee that the underlying frame of the canonical model satisfies the frame conditions of L.

We say that a formula or a set X of formulas is canonical

with respect to a property P of Kripke frames, if

  • X is valid in every frame that satisfies P,
  • for any normal modal logic L that contains X, the underlying frame of the canonical model of L satisfies P.

A union of canonical sets of formulas is itself canonical.

It follows from the preceding discussion that any logic axiomatized by

a canonical set of formulas is Kripke complete, and

compact.

The axioms T, 4, D, B, 5, H, G (and thus

any combination of them) are canonical. GL and Grz are not

canonical, because they are not compact. The axiom M by itself is

not canonical (Goldblatt, 1991), but the combined logic S4.1 (in

fact, even K4.1) is canonical.

In general, it is undecidable whether a given axiom is

canonical. We know a nice sufficient condition: Henrik Sahlqvist identified a broad class of formulas (now called

Sahlqvist formulas) such that

  • a Sahlqvist formula is canonical,
  • the class of frames corresponding to a Sahlqvist formula is first-order definable,
  • there is an algorithm that computes the corresponding frame condition to a given Sahlqvist formula.

This is a powerful criterion: for example, all axioms

listed above as canonical are (equivalent to) Sahlqvist formulas.

Finite model property

A logic has the finite model property (FMP) if it is complete

with respect to a class of finite frames. An application of this

notion is the decidability question: it

follows from

Post's theorem that a recursively axiomatized modal logic L

which has FMP is decidable, provided it is decidable whether a given

finite frame is a model of L. In particular, every finitely

axiomatizable logic with FMP is decidable.

There are various methods for establishing FMP for a given logic.

Refinements and extensions of the canonical model construction often

work, using tools such as filtration or

unravelling. As another possibility,

completeness proofs based on cut-free

sequent calculi usually produce finite models

directly.

Most of the modal systems used in practice (including all listed

above) have FMP.

In some cases, we can use FMP to prove Kripke completeness of a logic:

every normal modal logic is complete with respect to a class of

modal algebras, and a finite modal algebra can be transformed

into a Kripke frame. As an example, Robert Bull proved using this method

that every normal extension of S4.3 has FMP, and is Kripke

complete.

Multimodal logics

{{See also|Multimodal logic}}

Kripke semantics has a straightforward generalization to logics with

more than one modality. A Kripke frame for a language with

as the set of its necessity operators

consists of a non-empty set W equipped with binary relations

Ri for each i ∈ I. The definition of a

satisfaction relation is modified as follows:

if and only if

A simplified semantics, discovered by Tim Carlson, is often used for

polymodal provability logics. A Carlson model is a structure

with a single accessibility relation R, and subsets

Di ⊆ W for each modality. Satisfaction is

defined as

if and only if

Carlson models are easier to visualize and to work with than usual

polymodal Kripke models; there are, however, Kripke complete polymodal

logics which are Carlson incomplete.

Semantics of intuitionistic logic

Kripke semantics for the intuitionistic logic follows the same

principles as the semantics of modal logic, but it uses a different

definition of satisfaction.

An intuitionistic Kripke model is a triple

, where is a preordered Kripke frame, and satisfies the following conditions:

  • if p is a propositional variable, , and , then (persistency condition (cf. monotonicity)),
  • if and only if and ,
  • if and only if or ,
  • if and only if for all , implies ,
  • not .

The negation of A, ¬A, could be defined as an abbreviation for A → ⊥. If for all u such that wu, not u A, then w A → ⊥ is vacuously true, so w ¬A.

Intuitionistic logic is sound and complete with respect to its Kripke

semantics, and it has the finite model property.

Intuitionistic first-order logic

Let L be a first-order language. A Kripke

model of L is a triple

, where

is an intuitionistic Kripke frame, Mw is a

(classical) L-structure for each node w ∈ W, and

the following compatibility conditions hold whenever u ≤ v:

  • the domain of Mu is included in the domain of Mv,
  • realizations of function symbols in Mu and Mv agree on elements of Mu,
  • for each n-ary predicate P and elements a1,…,an ∈ Mu: if P(a1,…,an) holds in Mu, then it holds in Mv.

Given an evaluation e of variables by elements of Mw, we

define the satisfaction relation :

  • if and only if holds in Mw,
  • if and only if and ,
  • if and only if or ,
  • if and only if for all , implies ,
  • not ,
  • if and only if there exists an such that ,
  • if and only if for every and every , .

Here e(xa) is the evaluation which gives x the

value a, and otherwise agrees with e.

See a slightly different formalization in.[4]

Kripke–Joyal semantics

As part of the independent development of sheaf theory, it was realised around 1965 that Kripke semantics was intimately related to the treatment of existential quantification in topos theory.[5] That is, the 'local' aspect of existence for sections of a sheaf was a kind of logic of the 'possible'. Though this development was the work of a number of people, the name Kripke–Joyal semantics is often used in this connection.

Model constructions

As in classical model theory, there are methods for

constructing a new Kripke model from other models.

The natural homomorphisms in Kripke semantics are called

p-morphisms (which is short for pseudo-epimorphism, but the

latter term is rarely used). A p-morphism of Kripke frames

and is a mapping

such that

  • f preserves the accessibility relation, i.e., u R v implies f(uR’ f(v),
  • whenever f(uR’ v’, there is a v ∈ W such that u R v and f(v) = v’.

A p-morphism of Kripke models and

is a p-morphism of their

underlying frames , which

satisfies

if and only if , for any propositional variable p.

P-morphisms are a special kind of bisimulations. In general, a

bisimulation between frames and

is a relation

B ⊆ W × W’, which satisfies

the following “zig-zag” property:

  • if u B u’ and u R v, there exists v’ ∈ W’ such that v B v’ and u’ R’ v’,
  • if u B u’ and u’ R’ v’, there exists v ∈ W such that v B v’ and u R v.

A bisimulation of models is additionally required to preserve forcing

of atomic formulas:

if w B w’, then if and only if , for any propositional variable p.

The key property which follows from this definition is that

bisimulations (hence also p-morphisms) of models preserve the

satisfaction of all formulas, not only propositional variables.

We can transform a Kripke model into a tree using

unravelling. Given a model and a fixed

node w0 ∈ W, we define a model

, where W’ is the

set of all finite sequences

such

that wi R wi+1 for all

i < n, and if and only if

for a propositional variable

p. The definition of the accessibility relation R’

varies; in the simplest case we put

,

but many applications need the reflexive and/or transitive closure of

this relation, or similar modifications.

Filtration is a useful construction which uses to prove FMP for many logics. Let X be a set of

formulas closed under taking subformulas. An X-filtration of a

model is a mapping f from W to a model

such that

  • f is a surjection,
  • f preserves the accessibility relation, and (in both directions) satisfaction of variables p ∈ X,
  • if f(uR’ f(v) and , where , then .

It follows that f preserves satisfaction of all formulas from

X. In typical applications, we take f as the projection

onto the quotient of W over the relation

u ≡X v if and only if for all A ∈ X, if and only if .

As in the case of unravelling, the definition of the accessibility

relation on the quotient varies.

General frame semantics

The main defect of Kripke semantics is the existence of Kripke incomplete logics, and logics which are complete but not compact. It can be remedied by equipping Kripke frames with extra structure which restricts the set of possible valuations, using ideas from algebraic semantics. This gives rise to the general frame semantics.

Computer science applications

{{main|Kripke structure|state transition system|model checking}}

Blackburn et al. (2001) point out that because a relational structure is simply a set together with a collection of relations on that set, it is unsurprising that relational structures are to be found just about everywhere. As an example from theoretical computer science, they give labeled transition systems, which model program execution. Blackburn et al. thus claim because of this connection that modal languages are ideally suited in providing "internal, local perspective on relational structures." (p. xii)

History and terminology

{{Unreferenced section|date=October 2009}}

Similar work that predated Kripke's revolutionary semantic breakthroughs:

  • Rudolf Carnap seems to have been the first to have the idea that one can give a possible world semantics for the modalities of necessity and possibility by means of giving the valuation function a parameter that ranges over Leibnizian possible worlds. Bayart develops this idea further, but neither gave recursive definitions of satisfaction in the style introduced by Tarski;
  • J.C.C. McKinsey and Alfred Tarski developed an approach to modeling modal logics that is still influential in modern research, namely the algebraic approach, in which Boolean algebras with operators are used as models. Bjarni Jónsson and Tarski established the representability of Boolean algebras with operators in terms of frames. If the two ideas had been put together, the result would have been precisely frame models, which is to say Kripke models, years before Kripke. But no one (not even Tarski) saw the connection at the time.
  • Arthur Prior, building on unpublished work of C. A. Meredith, developed a translation of sentential modal logic into classical predicate logic that, if he had combined it with the usual model theory for the latter, would have produced a model theory equivalent to Kripke models for the former. But his approach was resolutely syntactic and anti-model-theoretic.
  • Stig Kanger gave a rather more complex approach to the interpretation of modal logic, but one that contains many of the key ideas of Kripke's approach. He first noted the relationship between conditions on accessibility relations and Lewis-style axioms for modal logic. Kanger failed, however, to give a completeness proof for his system;
  • Jaakko Hintikka gave a semantics in his papers introducing epistemic logic that is a simple variation of Kripke's semantics, equivalent to the characterisation of valuations by means of maximal consistent sets. He doesn't give inference rules for epistemic logic, and so cannot give a completeness proof;
  • Richard Montague had many of the key ideas contained in Kripke's work, but he did not regard them as significant, because he had no completeness proof, and so did not publish until after Kripke's papers had created a sensation in the logic community;
  • Evert Willem Beth presented a semantics of intuitionistic logic based on trees, which closely resembles Kripke semantics, except for using a more cumbersome definition of satisfaction.

See also

  • Alexandrov topology
  • Normal modal logic
  • Two dimensionalism

Notes

1. ^{{cite book |last=Shoham |first=Yoav |first2=Kevin |last2=Leyton-Brown |title=Multiagent Systems: Algorithmic, Game-Theoretic, and Logical Foundations |date=2008 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=0521899435 |page=397|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=bMR_qScakukC }}
2. ^{{cite book|last1=Gasquet|first1=Olivier|title=Kripke’s Worlds: An Introduction to Modal Logics via Tableaux|date=2013|publisher=Springer |isbn=3764385030|pages=14–16|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qFS-BAAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=false|accessdate=24 December 2014|display-authors=etal}}
3. ^{{cite book|last1=Giaquinto|first1=Marcus|title=The Search for Certainty : A Philosophical Account of Foundations of Mathematics: A Philosophical Account of Foundations of Mathematics|date=2002|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=019875244X|page=256|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gyNbrpYXzxoC&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=false|accessdate=24 December 2014}}
4. ^Intuitionistic Logic. Written by Joan Moschovakis. Published in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
5. ^{{cite book |authorlink=Robert Goldblatt |first=Robert |last=Goldblatt |chapter=A Kripke-Joyal Semantics for Noncommutative Logic in Quantales |chapterurl=http://homepages.ecs.vuw.ac.nz/~rob/papers/aiml11printed.pdf |format=PDF |editor-first=G. |editor-last=Governatori |editor2-first=I. |editor2-last=Hodkinson |editor3-first=Y. |editor3-last=Venema |title=Advances in Modal Logic |publisher=College Publications |location=London |year=2006 |isbn=1904987206 |pages=209–225 |volume=6}}

References

  • {{cite book |first=P. |last=Blackburn |author2link=Maarten de Rijke |first2=M. |last2=de Rijke |first3=Yde |last3=Venema |title=Modal Logic |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-n7uBgAAQBAJ |date=2002 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-316-10195-7}}
  • {{cite book |last=Bull |first=Robert A. |first2=K. |last2=Segerberg |chapter=Basic Modal Logic |editor-first=D.M. |editor-last=Gabbay |editor2-first=F. |editor2-last=Guenthner |series=Handbook of Philosophical Logic |volume=2 |title=Extensions of Classical Logic |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=IoTtCAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |date=2012 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-009-6259-0 |pages=1–88 |origyear=1984}}
  • {{cite book |first=A. |last=Chagrov |first2=M. |last2=Zakharyaschev |title=Modal Logic |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dhgi5NF4RtcC |year=1997 |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-853779-3}}
  • {{cite book |authorlink=Michael Dummett |first=Michael A. E. |last=Dummett |title=Elements of Intuitionism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JVFzknbGBVAC |year=2000 |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-850524-2 |edition=2nd}}
  • {{cite book |first=Melvin |last=Fitting |title=Intuitionistic Logic, Model Theory and Forcing |year=1969 |publisher=North-Holland |isbn=978-0-444-53418-7}}
  • {{cite book |authorlink=Robert Goldblatt |first=Robert |last=Goldblatt |chapter=Mathematical Modal Logic: a View of its Evolution |chapterurl=http://www.msor.vuw.ac.nz/~rob/papers/modalhist.pdf |format=PDF |editor-first=Dov M. |editor-last=Gabbay |editor2-first=John |editor2-last=Woods |title=Logic and the Modalities in the Twentieth Century |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gpwZYXsomEsC&pg=PP1 |date=2006 |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=978-0-08-046303-2 |pages=1–98 |series=Handbook of the History of Logic |volume=7}}
  • {{cite book |first=M.J. |last=Cresswell |first2=G.E. |last2=Hughes |title=A New Introduction to Modal Logic |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TkwrBgAAQBAJ |year=2012 |origyear=1996 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-134-80028-5}}
  • {{cite book |authorlink=Saunders Mac Lane |author2link=Ieke Moerdijk |first=Saunders |last=Mac Lane |first2=Ieke |last2=Moerdijk |title=Sheaves in Geometry and Logic: A First Introduction to Topos Theory |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LZWLBAAAQBAJ |year=2012 |origyear=1991 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4612-0927-0 }}
  • {{cite book |last=van Dalen |first=Dirk |origyear=1986 |chapter=Intuitionistic Logic |editor-first=Dov M. |editor-last=Gabbay |editor2-first=Franz |editor2-last=Guenthner |series=Handbook of Philosophical Logic |title=Alternatives to Classical Logic |chapterurl=https://books.google.com/books?id=NwDwCAAAQBAJ&pg=PA225 |year=2013 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-009-5203-4 |pages=225–339 |volume=3}}

External links

{{Commons category|Kripke models}}
  • {{cite web |first=James |last=Garson |title=Modal Logic |date= |work=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher= |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2001/entries/logic-modal}}
  • {{cite web |first=Joan |last=Moschovakis |title=Intuitionistic Logic |date= |work=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher= |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-intuitionistic/}}
  • {{cite book |first=V. |last=Detlovs |last2=Podnieks |first2=K. |chapter=4.4 Constructive Propositional Logic — Kripke Semantics |chapterurl=http://www.ltn.lv/~podnieks/mlog/ml4a.htm#s44 |editor= |title=Introduction to Mathematical Logic |publisher=University of Latvia |year= |url=https://dspace.lu.lv/dspace/handle/7/34986}} N.B: Constructive = intuitionistic.
  • {{cite web|first=John P.|last=Burgess|title=Kripke Models|date=|work=|publisher=|url=http://www.princeton.edu/~jburgess/Kripke1.doc|deadurl=yes|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20041020014707/http://www.princeton.edu/~jburgess/Kripke1.doc|archivedate=2004-10-20|df=}}
  • {{springer|title=Kripke models|id=p/k055850}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Kripke Semantics}}Kripke-Semantik

6 : Modal logic|Model theory|Mathematical logic|Philosophical logic|Sheaf theory|Non-classical logic

随便看

 

开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。

 

Copyright © 2023 OENC.NET All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/11/12 4:09:27