词条 | Lamarckism | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
释义 |
Lamarckism (or Lamarckian inheritance) is the hypothesis that an organism can pass on characteristics that it has acquired through use or disuse during its lifetime to its offspring. It is also known as the inheritance of acquired characteristics or soft inheritance. It is inaccurately[1][2] named after the French biologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829), who incorporated the action of soft inheritance into his evolutionary theories as a supplement to his concept of orthogenesis, a drive towards complexity. The theory is cited in textbooks to contrast with Darwinism. This paints a false picture of the history of biology, as Lamarck did not originate the idea of soft inheritance, which was known from the classical era onwards, and it was not the primary focus of Lamarck's theory of evolution. Further, in On the Origin of Species (1859), Charles Darwin supported the idea of "use and disuse inheritance", though rejecting other aspects of Lamarck's theory; and his pangenesis theory implied soft inheritance. Many researchers from the 1860s onwards attempted to find evidence for the theory, but these have all been explained away either by other mechanisms such as genetic contamination, or as fraud. On the other hand, August Weismann's experiment is now considered to have failed to disprove Lamarckism as it did not address use and disuse. Later, Mendelian genetics supplanted the notion of inheritance of acquired traits, eventually leading to the development of the modern synthesis, and the general abandonment of Lamarckism in biology. Despite this, interest in Lamarckism has continued. Studies in the field of epigenetics, genetics and somatic hypermutation have highlighted the possible inheritance of traits acquired by the previous generation. The characterization of these findings as Lamarckism has been disputed. The inheritance of the hologenome, consisting of the genomes of all an organism's symbiotic microbes as well as its own genome, is also somewhat Lamarckian in effect, though entirely Darwinian in its mechanisms. Early historyOriginsThe inheritance of acquired characteristics was proposed in ancient times, and remained a current idea for many centuries. The historian of science Conway Zirkle wrote in 1935 that:[3] {{quote|Lamarck was neither the first nor the most distinguished biologist to believe in the inheritance of acquired characters. He merely endorsed a belief which had been generally accepted for at least 2,200 years before his time and used it to explain how evolution could have taken place. The inheritance of acquired characters had been accepted previously by Hippocrates, Aristotle, Galen, Roger Bacon, Jerome Cardan, Levinus Lemnius, John Ray, Michael Adanson, Jo. Fried. Blumenbach and Erasmus Darwin among others.[1]}}Zirkle noted that Hippocrates described pangenesis, the theory that what is inherited derives from the whole body of the parent, whereas Aristotle thought it impossible; but that all the same, Aristotle implicitly agreed to the inheritance of acquired characteristics, giving the example of the inheritance of a scar, or of blindness, though noting that children do not always resemble their parents. Zirkle recorded that Pliny the Elder thought much the same. Zirkle also pointed out that stories involving the idea of inheritance of acquired characteristics appear numerous times in ancient mythology and the Bible, and persisted through to Rudyard Kipling's Just So Stories.[5] Erasmus Darwin's Zoonomia (c. 1795) suggested that warm-blooded animals develop from "one living filament... with the power of acquiring new parts" in response to stimuli, with each round of "improvements" being inherited by successive generations.[2] Darwin's pangenesis{{main|Pangenesis}}Charles Darwin's On the Origin of Species proposed natural selection as the main mechanism for development of species, but did not rule out a variant of Lamarckism as a supplementary mechanism.[3] Darwin called this pangenesis, and explained it in the final chapter of his book The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication (1868), after describing numerous examples to demonstrate what he considered to be the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Pangenesis, which he emphasised was a hypothesis, was based on the idea that somatic cells would, in response to environmental stimulation (use and disuse), throw off 'gemmules' or 'pangenes' which travelled around the body, though not necessarily in the bloodstream. These pangenes were microscopic particles that supposedly contained information about the characteristics of their parent cell, and Darwin believed that they eventually accumulated in the germ cells where they could pass on to the next generation the newly acquired characteristics of the parents.[4][5]Darwin's half-cousin, Francis Galton, carried out experiments on rabbits, with Darwin's cooperation, in which he transfused the blood of one variety of rabbit into another variety in the expectation that its offspring would show some characteristics of the first. They did not, and Galton declared that he had disproved Darwin's hypothesis of pangenesis, but Darwin objected, in a letter to the scientific journal Nature, that he had done nothing of the sort, since he had never mentioned blood in his writings. He pointed out that he regarded pangenesis as occurring in protozoa and plants, which have no blood, as well as in animals.[6] Lamarck's evolutionary framework{{further|Jean-Baptiste Lamarck#Lamarckian evolution}}Between 1800 and 1830, Lamarck proposed a systematic theoretical framework for understanding evolution. He saw evolution as comprising four laws:[7][8]
Lamarck's discussion of heredityIn 1830, in an aside from his evolutionary framework, Lamarck briefly mentioned two traditional ideas in his discussion of heredity, in his day considered to be generally true. The first was the idea of use versus disuse; he theorized that individuals lose characteristics they do not require, or use, and develop characteristics that are useful. The second was to argue that the acquired traits were heritable. He gave as an imagined illustration the idea that when giraffes stretch their necks to reach leaves high in trees, they would strengthen and gradually lengthen their necks. These giraffes would then have offspring with slightly longer necks. In the same way, he argued, a blacksmith, through his work, strengthens the muscles in his arms, and thus his sons would have similar muscular development when they mature. Lamarck stated the following two laws:[13]
English translation:
In essence, a change in the environment brings about change in "needs" (besoins), resulting in change in behavior, bringing change in organ usage and development, bringing change in form over time—and thus the gradual transmutation of the species. However, as the evolutionary biologists and historians of science Michael Ghiselin and Steven Jay Gould have pointed out, these ideas were not original to Lamarck.[1][11] Weismann's experimentThe idea that germline cells contain information that passes to each generation unaffected by experience and independent of the somatic (body) cells, came to be referred to as the Weismann barrier, as it would make Lamarckian inheritance from changes to the body difficult or impossible.[12] August Weismann conducted the experiment of removing the tails of 68 white mice, and those of their offspring over five generations, and reporting that no mice were born in consequence without a tail or even with a shorter tail. In 1889, he stated that "901 young were produced by five generations of artificially mutilated parents, and yet there was not a single example of a rudimentary tail or of any other abnormality in this organ."[13] The experiment, and the theory behind it, were thought at the time to be a refutation of Lamarckism.[12]However, the experiment's effectiveness in refuting Lamarck's hypothesis is doubtful, as it did not address the use and disuse of characteristics in response to the environment. The biologist Peter Gauthier noted in 1990 that:[22] Can Weismann's experiment be considered a case of disuse? Lamarck proposed that when an organ was not used, it slowly, and very gradually atrophied. In time, over the course of many generations, it would gradually disappear as it was inherited in its modified form in each successive generation. Cutting the tails off mice does not seem to meet the qualifications of disuse, but rather falls in a category of accidental misuse... Lamarck's hypothesis has never been proven experimentally and there is no known mechanism to support the idea that somatic change, however acquired, can in some way induce a change in the germplasm. On the other hand it is difficult to disprove Lamarck's idea experimentally, and it seems that Weismann's experiment fails to provide the evidence to deny the Lamarckian hypothesis, since it lacks a key factor, namely the willful exertion of the animal in overcoming environmental obstacles.[14] The biologist and historian of science Michael Ghiselin also considered the Weismann tail-chopping experiment to have no bearing on the Lamarckian hypothesis, writing in 1994 that:[1] The acquired characteristics that figured in Lamarck's thinking were changes that resulted from an individual's own drives and actions, not from the actions of external agents. Lamarck was not concerned with wounds, injuries or mutilations, and nothing that Lamarck had set forth was tested or "disproven" by the Weismann tail-chopping experiment.[1] Textbook LamarckismThe identification of Lamarckism with the inheritance of acquired characteristics is regarded by evolutionary biologists including Michael Ghiselin as a falsified artifact of the subsequent history of evolutionary thought, repeated in textbooks without analysis, and wrongly contrasted with a falsified picture of Darwin's thinking. Ghiselin notes that "Darwin accepted the inheritance of acquired characteristics, just as Lamarck did, and Darwin even thought that there was some experimental evidence to support it."[15] American paleontologist and historian of science Stephen Jay Gould wrote that in the late 19th century, evolutionists "re-read Lamarck, cast aside the guts of it ... and elevated one aspect of the mechanics—inheritance of acquired characters—to a central focus it never had for Lamarck himself."[16] He argued that "the restriction of 'Lamarckism' to this relatively small and non-distinctive corner of Lamarck's thought must be labelled as more than a misnomer, and truly a discredit to the memory of a man and his much more comprehensive system."[17][18] Neo-LamarckismContext{{further|Eclipse of Darwinism}}The period of the history of evolutionary thought between Darwin's death in the 1880s, and the foundation of population genetics in the 1920s and the beginnings of the modern evolutionary synthesis in the 1930s, is called the eclipse of Darwinism by some historians of science. During that time many scientists and philosophers accepted the reality of evolution but doubted whether natural selection was the main evolutionary mechanism.[19] Among the most popular alternatives were theories involving the inheritance of characteristics acquired during an organism's lifetime. Scientists who felt that such Lamarckian mechanisms were the key to evolution were called neo-Lamarckians. They included the British botanist George Henslow (1835–1925), who studied the effects of environmental stress on the growth of plants, in the belief that such environmentally-induced variation might explain much of plant evolution, and the American entomologist Alpheus Spring Packard, Jr., who studied blind animals living in caves and wrote a book in 1901 about Lamarck and his work.[20][21] Also included were paleontologists like Edward Drinker Cope and Alpheus Hyatt, who observed that the fossil record showed orderly, almost linear, patterns of development that they felt were better explained by Lamarckian mechanisms than by natural selection. Some people, including Cope and the Darwin critic Samuel Butler, felt that inheritance of acquired characteristics would let organisms shape their own evolution, since organisms that acquired new habits would change the use patterns of their organs, which would kick-start Lamarckian evolution. They considered this philosophically superior to Darwin's mechanism of random variation acted on by selective pressures. Lamarckism also appealed to those, like the philosopher Herbert Spencer and the German anatomist Ernst Haeckel, who saw evolution as an inherently progressive process.[20] The German zoologist Theodor Eimer combined Larmarckism with ideas about orthogenesis, the idea that evolution is directed towards a goal.[22] With the development of the modern synthesis of the theory of evolution, and a lack of evidence for a mechanism for acquiring and passing on new characteristics, or even their heritability, Lamarckism largely fell from favour. Unlike neo-Darwinism, neo-Lamarckism is a loose grouping of largely heterodox theories and mechanisms that emerged after Lamarck's time, rather than a coherent body of theoretical work.[23] 19th centuryNeo-Lamarckian versions of evolution were widespread in the late 19th century. The idea that living things could to some degree choose the characteristics that would be inherited allowed them to be in charge of their own destiny as opposed to the Darwinian view, which placed them at the mercy of the environment. Such ideas were more popular than natural selection in the late 19th century as it made it possible for biological evolution to fit into a framework of a divine or naturally willed plan, thus the neo-Lamarckian view of evolution was often advocated by proponents of orthogenesis.[24] According to the historian of science Peter J. Bowler, writing in 2003: {{blockquote|One of the most emotionally compelling arguments used by the neo-Lamarckians of the late nineteenth century was the claim that Darwinism was a mechanistic theory which reduced living things to puppets driven by heredity. The selection theory made life into a game of Russian roulette, where life or death was predetermined by the genes one inherited. The individual could do nothing to mitigate bad heredity. Lamarckism, in contrast, allowed the individual to choose a new habit when faced with an environmental challenge and shape the whole future course of evolution.[25]}}{{anchor|Experiments}}Scientists from the 1860s onwards conducted numerous experiments that purported to show Lamarckian inheritance. Some examples are described in the table.
Early 20th centuryA century after Lamarck, scientists and philosophers continued to seek mechanisms and evidence for the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Experiments were sometimes reported as successful, but from the beginning these were either criticised on scientific grounds or shown to be fakes.[43][44][45][46][47] For instance, in 1906, the philosopher Eugenio Rignano argued for a version that he called "centro-epigenesis",[48][49][50][51][52][53] but it was rejected by most scientists.[54] Some of the experimental approaches are described in the table.
Late 20th centuryThe British anthropologist Frederic Wood Jones and the South African paleontologist Robert Broom supported a neo-Lamarckian view of human evolution. The German anthropologist Hermann Klaatsch relied on a neo-Lamarckian model of evolution to try and explain the origin of bipedalism. Neo-Lamarckism remained influential in biology until the 1940s when the role of natural selection was reasserted in evolution as part of the modern evolutionary synthesis.[86] Herbert Graham Cannon, a British zoologist, defended Lamarckism in his 1959 book Lamarck and Modern Genetics.[87] In the 1960s, "biochemical Lamarckism" was advocated by the embryologist Paul Wintrebert.[88]Neo-Lamarckism was dominant in French biology for more than a century. French scientists who supported neo-Lamarckism included Edmond Perrier (1844–1921), Alfred Giard (1846–1908), Gaston Bonnier (1853–1922) and Pierre-Paul Grassé (1895–1985). They followed two traditions, one mechanistic, one vitalistic after Henri Bergson's philosophy of evolution.[89] In 1987, Ryuichi Matsuda coined the term "pan-environmentalism" for his evolutionary theory which he saw as a fusion of Darwinism with neo-Lamarckism. He held that heterochrony is a main mechanism for evolutionary change and that novelty in evolution can be generated by genetic assimilation.[90][91] His views were criticized by Arthur M. Shapiro for providing no solid evidence for his theory. Shapiro noted that "Matsuda himself accepts too much at face value and is prone to wish-fulfilling interpretation."[91] Ideological neo-LamarckismA form of Lamarckism was revived in the Soviet Union of the 1930s when Trofim Lysenko promoted the ideologically-driven research programme, Lysenkoism; this suited the ideological opposition of Joseph Stalin to genetics. Lysenkoism influenced Soviet agricultural policy which in turn was later blamed for crop failures.[92] CritiqueGeorge Gaylord Simpson in his book Tempo and Mode in Evolution (1944) claimed that experiments in heredity have failed to corroborate any Lamarckian process.[93] Simpson noted that neo-Lamarckism "stresses a factor that Lamarck rejected: inheritance of direct effects of the environment" and neo-Lamarckism is closer to Darwin's pangenesis than Lamarck's views.[94] Simpson wrote, "the inheritance of acquired characters, failed to meet the tests of observation and has been almost universally discarded by biologists."[95]Botanist Conway Zirkle pointed out that Lamarck did not originate the hypothesis that acquired characteristics could be inherited, so it is incorrect to refer to it as Lamarckism: What Lamarck really did was to accept the hypothesis that acquired characters were heritable, a notion which had been held almost universally for well over two thousand years and which his contemporaries accepted as a matter of course, and to assume that the results of such inheritance were cumulative from generation to generation, thus producing, in time, new species. His individual contribution to biological theory consisted in his application to the problem of the origin of species of the view that acquired characters were inherited and in showing that evolution could be inferred logically from the accepted biological hypotheses. He would doubtless have been greatly astonished to learn that a belief in the inheritance of acquired characters is now labeled "Lamarckian," although he would almost certainly have felt flattered if evolution itself had been so designated.[96]Peter Medawar wrote regarding Lamarckism, "very few professional biologists believe that anything of the kind occurs—or can occur—but the notion persists for a variety of nonscientific reasons." Medawar stated there is no known mechanism by which an adaptation acquired in an individual's lifetime can be imprinted on the genome and Lamarckian inheritance is not valid unless it excludes the possibility of natural selection but this has not been demonstrated in any experiment.[97] Martin Gardner wrote in his book Fads and Fallacies in the Name of Science (1957): A host of experiments have been designed to test Lamarckianism. All that have been verified have proved negative. On the other hand, tens of thousands of experiments— reported in the journals and carefully checked and rechecked by geneticists throughout the world— have established the correctness of the gene-mutation theory beyond all reasonable doubt... In spite of the rapidly increasing evidence for natural selection, Lamarck has never ceased to have loyal followers.... There is indeed a strong emotional appeal in the thought that every little effort an animal puts forth is somehow transmitted to his progeny.[98] According to Ernst Mayr, any Lamarckian theory involving the inheritance of acquired characters has been refuted as "DNA does not directly participate in the making of the phenotype and that the phenotype, in turn, does not control the composition of the DNA."[99] Peter J. Bowler has written that although many early scientists took Lamarckism seriously, it was discredited by genetics in the early twentieth century.[100] Mechanisms resembling LamarckismStudies in the field of epigenetics, genetics and somatic hypermutation[120][121] have highlighted the possible inheritance of traits acquired by the previous generation.[101][102][103][104][105] However, the characterization of these findings as Lamarckism has been disputed.[106][107][108][109] Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance{{further|Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance|Contribution of epigenetic modifications to evolution}}Epigenetic inheritance has been argued by scientists including Eva Jablonka and Marion J. Lamb to be Lamarckian.[110] Epigenetics is based on hereditary elements other than genes that pass into the germ cells. These include methylation patterns in DNA and chromatin marks on histone proteins, both involved in gene regulation. These marks are responsive to environmental stimuli, differentially affect gene expression, and are adaptive, with phenotypic effects that persist for some generations. The mechanism may also enable the inheritance of behavioral traits, for example in chickens[111][112][113] rats[114][115] and human populations that have experienced starvation, DNA methylation resulting in altered gene function in both the starved population and their offspring.[116] Methylation similarly mediates epigenetic inheritance in plants such as rice.[117][118] Small RNA molecules, too, may mediate inherited resistance to infection.[119][120][121] Handel and Romagopalan commented that "epigenetics allows the peaceful co-existence of Darwinian and Lamarckian evolution."[122]Joseph Springer and Dennis Holley commented in 2013 that:[144] Lamarck and his ideas were ridiculed and discredited. In a strange twist of fate, Lamarck may have the last laugh. Epigenetics, an emerging field of genetics, has shown that Lamarck may have been at least partially correct all along. It seems that reversible and heritable changes can occur without a change in DNA sequence (genotype) and that such changes may be induced spontaneously or in response to environmental factors—Lamarck's "acquired traits." Determining which observed phenotypes are genetically inherited and which are environmentally induced remains an important and ongoing part of the study of genetics, developmental biology, and medicine.[123] The prokaryotic CRISPR system and Piwi-interacting RNA could be classified as Lamarckian, within a Darwinian framework.[124][125] However, the significance of epigenetics in evolution is uncertain. Critics such as the evolutionary biologist Jerry Coyne point out that epigenetic inheritance lasts for only a few generations, so it is not a stable basis for evolutionary change.[126][127][128][129] The evolutionary biologist T. Ryan Gregory contends that epigenetic inheritance should not be considered Lamarckian. According to Gregory, Lamarck did not claim that the environment directly affected living things. Instead, Lamarck "argued that the environment created needs to which organisms responded by using some features more and others less, that this resulted in those features being accentuated or attenuated, and that this difference was then inherited by offspring." Gregory has stated that Lamarckian evolution in epigenetics is more like Darwin's point of view than Lamarck's.[106] In 2007, David Haig wrote that research into epigenetic processes does allow a Lamarckian element in evolution but the processes do not challenge the main tenets of the modern evolutionary synthesis as modern Lamarckians have claimed. Haig argued for the primacy of DNA and evolution of epigenetic switches by natural selection.[130] Haig has written that there is a "visceral attraction" to Lamarckian evolution from the public and some scientists, as it posits the world with a meaning, in which organisms can shape their own evolutionary destiny.[131] Thomas Dickens and Qazi Rahman (2012) have argued that epigenetic mechanisms such as DNA methylation and histone modification are genetically inherited under the control of natural selection and do not challenge the modern synthesis. They dispute the claims of Jablonka and Lamb on Lamarckian epigenetic processes.[132] In 2015, Khursheed Iqbal and colleagues discovered that although "endocrine disruptors exert direct epigenetic effects in the exposed fetal germ cells, these are corrected by reprogramming events in the next generation."[133] Also in 2015, Adam Weiss argued that bringing back Lamarck in the context of epigenetics is misleading, commenting, "We should remember [Lamarck] for the good he contributed to science, not for things that resemble his theory only superficially. Indeed, thinking of CRISPR and other phenomena as Lamarckian only obscures the simple and elegant way evolution really works."[134] Somatic hypermutation and reverse transcription to germlineIn the 1970s, the Australian immunologist Edward J. Steele developed a neo-Lamarckian theory of somatic hypermutation within the immune system and coupled it to the reverse transcription of RNA derived from body cells to the DNA of germline cells. This reverse transcription process supposedly enabled characteristics or bodily changes acquired during a lifetime to be written back into the DNA and passed on to subsequent generations.[135][136] The mechanism was meant to explain why homologous DNA sequences from the VDJ gene regions of parent mice were found in their germ cells and seemed to persist in the offspring for a few generations. The mechanism involved the somatic selection and clonal amplification of newly acquired antibody gene sequences generated via somatic hypermutation in B-cells. The messenger RNA products of these somatically novel genes were captured by retroviruses endogenous to the B-cells and were then transported through the bloodstream where they could breach the Weismann or soma-germ barrier and reverse transcribe the newly acquired genes into the cells of the germ line, in the manner of Darwin's pangenes.[137][138][139] The historian of biology Peter J. Bowler noted in 1989 that other scientists had been unable to reproduce his results, and described the scientific consensus at the time:[140] {{quote|There is no feedback of information from the proteins to the DNA, and hence no route by which characteristics acquired in the body can be passed on through the genes. The work of Ted Steele (1979) provoked a flurry of interest in the possibility that there might, after all, be ways in which this reverse flow of information could take place. ... [His] mechanism did not, in fact, violate the principles of molecular biology, but most biologists were suspicious of Steele's claims, and attempts to reproduce his results have failed.[140]}}Bowler commented that "[Steele's] work was bitterly criticized at the time by biologists who doubted his experimental results and rejected his hypothetical mechanism as implausible."[140] Hologenome theory of evolution{{further|hologenome theory of evolution}}The hologenome theory of evolution, while Darwinian, has Lamarckian aspects. An individual animal or plant lives in symbiosis with many microorganisms, and together they have a "hologenome" consisting of all their genomes. The hologenome can vary like any other genome by mutation, sexual recombination, and chromosome rearrangement, but in addition it can vary when populations of microorganisms increase or decrease (resembling Lamarckian use and disuse), and when it gains new kinds of microorganism (resembling Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics). These changes are then passed on to offspring.[141] The mechanism is largely uncontroversial, and natural selection does sometimes occur at whole system (hologenome) level, but it is not clear that this is always the case.[142] Baldwin effect{{further|Baldwin effect}}The Baldwin effect, named after the psychologist James Mark Baldwin by George Gaylord Simpson in 1953, proposes that the ability to learn new behaviours can improve an animal's reproductive success, and hence the course of natural selection on its genetic makeup. Simpson stated that the mechanism was "not inconsistent with the modern synthesis" of evolutionary theory,[143] though he doubted that it occurred very often, or could be proven to occur. He noted that the Baldwin effect provide a reconciliation between the neo-Darwinian and neo-Lamarckian approaches, something that the modern synthesis had seemed to render unnecessary. In particular, the effect allows animals to adapt to a new stress in the environment through behavioural changes, followed by genetic change. This somewhat resembles Lamarckism but without requiring animals to inherit characteristics acquired by their parents.[144] The Baldwin effect is broadly accepted by Darwinists.[145] In sociocultural evolutionWithin the history of technology, Lamarckism has been used in linking cultural development to human evolution by classifying artefacts as extensions of human anatomy: in other words, as the acquired cultural characteristics of human beings. Ben Cullen has shown that a strong element of Lamarckism exists in sociocultural evolution.[146]{{-}} Lamarckism was influential in some non -Western nations like China, for it even became a part of the Chinese translation of the Origin of Species.[147] References1. ^1 {{cite journal | last1=Zirkle | first1=Conway | authorlink=Conway Zirkle | year=1935 | title=The Inheritance of Acquired Characters and the Provisional Hypothesis of Pangenesis| journal=The American Naturalist | volume=69 | issue=724| pages=417–445 | doi=10.1086/280617}} 2. ^{{harvnb|Darwin|1794–1796|loc=Vol I, section XXXIX}} 3. ^{{harvnb|Desmond|Moore|1991|p=617}}: "But Darwin was {{sic|hide=y|loath}} to let go of the notion that a well-used and strengthened organ could be inherited." 4. ^{{cite journal |last=Darwin |first=Charles |authorlink=Charles Darwin |date=April 27, 1871 |title=Pangenesis |journal=Nature |volume=3 |issue=78 |pages=502–503 |bibcode=1871Natur...3..502D |doi=10.1038/003502a0}} 5. ^{{cite journal |author=Holterhoff, Kate |date=2014 |title=The History and Reception of Charles Darwin's Hypothesis of Pangenesis |journal=Journal of the History of Biology |volume=47 |issue=4 |pages=661–695 |doi=10.1007/s10739-014-9377-0}} 6. ^{{Cite journal |last=Liu |first=Yongsheng |date=2008 |title=A new perspective on Darwin's Pangenesis |journal=Biological Reviews |volume=83 |issue=2 |pages=141–149 |doi=10.1111/j.1469-185x.2008.00036.x|pmid=18429766 }} 7. ^{{cite book |author=Larson, Edward J. |date=2004 |title=A Growing sense of progress |work=Evolution: The remarkable history of a Scientific Theory |publisher=Modern Library |pages=38–41}} 8. ^{{cite book | last=Gould | first=Stephen | title=The lying stones of Marrakech : penultimate reflections in natural history | publisher=Vintage | year=2001 | isbn=978-0-09-928583-0 | pages=119–121}} 9. ^1 2 {{harvnb|Lamarck|1830|loc=p. 235}} 10. ^{{harvnb|Lamarck|1914|p=113}} 11. ^{{harvnb|Gould|2002}} 12. ^1 {{cite book |last=Romanes |first=George John |title=An examination of Weismannism |publisher=Open Court |year=1893 |url=https://openlibrary.org/books/OL23380098M/An_examination_of_Weismannism}} 13. ^{{harvnb|Weismann|1889|loc="The Supposed Transmission of Mutilations" (1888), p. 432}} 14. ^1 {{cite journal |last=Gauthier |first=Peter |date=March–May 1990 |title=Does Weismann's Experiment Constitute a Refutation of the Lamarckian Hypothesis? |journal=BIOS |volume=61 |number=1/2 |pages=6–8 |jstor=4608123}} 15. ^1 2 3 4 5 {{cite journal |last1=Ghiselin |first1=Michael T. |title=The Imaginary Lamarck: A Look at Bogus "History" in Schoolbooks |url=http://www.textbookleague.org/54marck.htm |journal=The Textbook Letter |issue=September–October 1994 |date=1994 |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20001012042617/http://www.textbookleague.org/54marck.htm |archivedate=12 October 2000 |deadurl=no}} 16. ^{{harvnb|Gould|1980|p=66}} 17. ^1 {{harvnb|Gould|2002|pp=177–178}} 18. ^{{cite magazine |last=Gould |first=Stephen Jay |authorlink=Stephen Jay Gould |date=October 4, 1979 |title=Another Look at Lamarck |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kHHYOtogBEgC&pg=PA38&lpg=PA38 |magazine=New Scientist |volume=84 |issue=1175 |pages=38–40 |accessdate=2015-11-09}} 19. ^{{harvnb|Quammen|2006|p=216}} 20. ^1 {{harvnb|Bowler|2003|pp=236–244}} 21. ^{{harvnb|Quammen|2006|pp=218, 220}} 22. ^{{harvnb|Quammen|2006|p=221}} 23. ^{{Cite book |title=Evolution: The History of an Idea |last=Bowler |first=Peter J. |publisher=University of California Press |year=1989 |origyear=1983 |edition=Revised |isbn=978-0520063860 |pages=257, 264, 279–280}} 24. ^{{harvnb|Bowler|1992}} 25. ^{{harvnb|Bowler|2003|p=367}} 26. ^{{harvnb|Mumford|1921|p=209}} 27. ^{{harvnb|Mason|1956|p=343}} 28. ^{{harvnb|Burkhardt|1995|p=166}} 29. ^{{harvnb|Raitiere|2012|p=299}} 30. ^{{harvnb|Linville|Kelly|1906|p=108}} 31. ^{{harvnb|Aminoff|2011|p=192}} 32. ^{{harvnb|Kohler|2002|p=167}} 33. ^{{cite journal |last=Cunningham |first=Joseph Thomas |authorlink=Joseph Thomas Cunningham |year=1891 |title=An Experiment concerning the Absence of Color from the lower Sides of Flat-fishes |journal=Zoologischer Anzeiger |volume=14 |pages=27–32}} 34. ^{{cite journal |last=Cunningham |first=Joseph Thomas |title=Researches on the Coloration of the Skins of Flat Fishes |date=May 1893 |journal=Journal of the Marine Biological Association of the United Kingdom |volume=3 |issue=1 |pages=111–118 |doi=10.1017/S0025315400049596}} 35. ^{{cite journal |last=Cunningham |first=Joseph Thomas |title=Additional Evidence on the Influence of Light in producing Pigments on the Lower Sides of Flat Fishes |date=May 1895 |journal=Journal of the Marine Biological Association of the United Kingdom |volume=4 |pages=53–59 |doi=10.1017/S0025315400050761|url=http://plymsea.ac.uk/146/1/Additional_evidence_on_the_influence_of_light_in_producing_pigments_on_the_lower_sides_of_flat_fishes.pdf }} 36. ^{{cite magazine |last=Moore |first=Eldon |date=September 15, 1928 |title=The New View of Mendelism |url=http://archive.spectator.co.uk/article/15th-september-1928/25/the-new-view-of-mendelism |magazine=The Spectator |type=Book review |volume=141 |issue=5229 |page=337 |accessdate=2015-10-24}} Review of Modern Biology (1928) by J. T. Cunningham. 37. ^{{harvnb|Cock|Forsdyke|2008|pp=132–133}} 38. ^{{harvnb|Morgan|1903|pp=257–259}} 39. ^{{harvnb|Goldschmidt|1940|pp=266–267}} 40. ^Burkhardt 1998, "Lamarckism in Britain and the United States", p. 348 41. ^{{harvnb|Forel|1934|p=36}} 42. ^{{cite journal |last=Packard |first=A. S. |authorlink=Alpheus Spring Packard |date=July 10, 1896 |title=Handbuch der paläarktischen Gross-Schmetterlinge für Forscher und Sammler. Zweite gänzlich umgearbeitete und durch Studien zur Descendenztheorie erweitete Auflage, etc |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eMY-AQAAIAAJ&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=false |journal=Science |type=Book review |volume=4 |issue=80 |pages=52–54 |doi=10.1126/science.4.80.52-c}} Review of Handbuch der paläarktischen Gross-Schmetterlinge für Forscher und Sammler (1896) by Maximilian Rudolph Standfuss. 43. ^1 {{harvnb|Delage|Goldsmith|1912|p=210}} 44. ^1 {{harvnb|Kohler|2002|pp=202–204}} 45. ^1 {{harvnb|Mitman|1992|p=219}} 46. ^1 {{harvnb|Bowler|2003|pp=245–246}} 47. ^1 {{harvnb|Medawar|1985|p=168}} 48. ^{{harvnb|Rignano|1906}} 49. ^{{harvnb|Rignano|Harvey|1911}} 50. ^{{cite journal |last=Eastwood |first=M. Lightfoot |date=October 1912 |title=Reviewed Work: Eugenio Rignano Upon the Inheritance of Acquired Characters by C.H. Harvey |journal=International Journal of Ethics |volume=23 |pages=117–118 |number=1 |jstor=2377122 |doi=10.1086/206715}} 51. ^{{harvnb|Newman|1921|p=335}} 52. ^{{harvnb|Rignano|1926}} 53. ^{{cite journal |last=Carmichael |first=Leonard |authorlink=Leonard Carmichael |date=December 23, 1926 |title=Reviewed Work: Biological Memory by Eugenio Rignano, E. W. MacBride |journal=The Journal of Philosophy |volume=23 |issue=26 |pages=718–720 |jstor=2014451 |doi=10.2307/2014451 }} 54. ^{{cite journal |author= |date=August 8, 1912 |title=(1) Upon the Inheritance of Acquired Characters (2) Biological Aspects of Human Problems |journal=Nature |type=Book review |volume=89 |issue=2232 |pages=576–578 |doi=10.1038/089576a0 |bibcode=1912Natur..89..576.}} 55. ^{{cite journal |last=Bateson |first=William |authorlink=William Bateson |date=July 3, 1919 |title=Dr. Kammerer's Testimony to the Inheritance of Acquired Characters |journal=Nature |type=Letter to editor |volume=103 |issue=2592 |pages=344–345 |doi=10.1038/103344b0 |bibcode=1919Natur.103..344B }} 56. ^{{harvnb|Bateson|1913|pp=[https://archive.org/stream/problemsofgeneti00bate#page/219/mode/2up 219–227]}} 57. ^Weinstein 1998, "A Note on W. L. Tower's Lepinotarsa Work," pp. 352–353 58. ^{{cite journal |last=MacBride |first=Ernest |authorlink=Ernest MacBride |date=January 1924 |title=The work of tornier as affording a possible explanation of the causes of mutations |journal=The Eugenics Review |volume=15 |issue=4 |pages=545–555 |pmc=2942563 |pmid=21259774}} 59. ^{{harvnb|Cunningham|1928|pp=84–97}} 60. ^{{cite journal |last=Sladden |first=Dorothy E. |date=May 1930 |title=Experimental Distortion of Development in Amphibian Tadpoles |journal=Proceedings of the Royal Society B |volume=106 |issue=744 |pages=318–325 |doi=10.1098/rspb.1930.0031 }} 61. ^{{cite journal |last=Sladden |first=Dorothy E. |date=November 1932 |title=Experimental Distortion of Development in Amphibian Tadpoles. Part II |journal=Proceedings of the Royal Society B |volume=112 |issue=774 |pages=1–12 |doi=10.1098/rspb.1932.0072}} 62. ^{{harvnb|Blumberg|2010|pp=69–70}} 63. ^{{harvnb|Young|1922|p=249}} 64. ^{{harvnb|Child|1945|pp=146–173}} 65. ^{{cite journal |last1=Guyer |first1=Michael F. |authorlink1=Michael F. Guyer |last2=Smith |first2=E. A. |date=March 1920 |title=Transmission of Eye-Defects Induced in Rabbits by Means of Lens-Sensitized Fowl-Serum |journal=PNAS |volume=6 |issue=3 |pages=134–136 |bibcode=1920PNAS....6..134G |doi=10.1073/pnas.6.3.134 |pmc=1084447 |pmid=16576477}} 66. ^{{harvnb|Medawar|1985|p=169}} 67. ^{{harvnb|Moore|2002|p=330}} 68. ^{{cite journal |last=McDougall |first=William |authorlink=William McDougall (psychologist) |date=April 1938 |title=Fourth Report on a Lamarckian Experiment |department=General Section |journal=British Journal of Psychology |volume=28 |issue=4 |pages=365–395 |doi=10.1111/j.2044-8295.1938.tb00882.x}} 69. ^{{cite journal |last=Pantin |first=Carl F. A. |authorlink=Carl Pantin |date=November 1957 |title=Oscar Werner Tiegs. 1897-1956 |journal=Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the Royal Society |volume=3 |pages=247–255 |doi=10.1098/rsbm.1957.0017}} 70. ^{{cite journal |last1=Agar |first1=Wilfred E. |authorlink1=Wilfred Eade Agar |last2=Drummond |first2=Frank H. |last3=Tiegs |first3=Oscar W. |authorlink3=Oscar Werner Tiegs |date=July 1935 |title=A First Report on a Test of McDougall'S Lamarckian Experiment on the Training of Rats |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/12/3/191.short |journal=The Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=12 |issue=3 |pages=191–211}} 71. ^{{cite journal |last1=Agar |first1=Wilfred E. |last2=Drummond |first2=Frank H. |last3=Tiegs |first3=Oscar W. |date=October 1942 |title=Second Report on a Test of McDougall's Lamarckian Experiment on the Training of Rats |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/19/2/158.short |journal=The Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=19 |issue=2 |pages=158–167}} 72. ^{{cite journal |last1=Agar |first1=Wilfred E. |last2=Drummond |first2=Frank H. |last3=Tiegs |first3=Oscar W. |date=June 1948 |title=Third Report on a Test of McDougall'S Lamarckian Experiment on the Training of Rats |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/25/2/103.short |journal=The Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=25 |issue=2 |pages=103–122 |accessdate=2015-10-28}} 73. ^{{cite journal |last1=Agar |first1=Wilfred E. |last2=Drummond |first2=Frank H. |last3=Tiegs |first3=Oscar W. |last4=Gunson |first4=Mary M. |date=September 1954 |title=Fourth (Final) Report on a Test of McDougall'S Lamarckian Experiment on the Training of Rats |url=http://jeb.biologists.org/content/31/3/307.short |journal=The Journal of Experimental Biology |volume=31 |issue=3 |pages=308–321}} 74. ^{{harvnb|Hagen|2002|p=144}}: "During the 1920s, the entomologist J. W. Heslop-Harrison published experimental data supporting his claim that chemicals in soot caused widespread mutations from light winged to the dark winged form. Because these mutations were supposedly passed on to subsequent generations, Harrison claimed that he had documented a case of inheritance of acquired traits. Other biologists failed to replicate Harrison's results, and R. A. Fisher pointed out that Harrison's hypothesis required a mutation rate far higher than any previously reported." 75. ^{{harvnb|Moore|Decker|2008|p=203}} 76. ^{{harvnb|McDougall|1934|p=180}} 77. ^{{cite journal |last1=Macdowell |first=E. Carleton |last2=Vicari |first2=Emilia M. |date=May 1921 |title=Alcoholism and the behavior of white rats. I. The influence of alcoholic grandparents upon maze-behavior |journal=Journal of Experimental Zoology |volume=33 |issue=1 |pages=208–291 |doi=10.1002/jez.1400330107}} 78. ^{{cite journal |last=Griffith |first1=Coleman R. |authorlink=Coleman Griffith |date=November–December 1920 |title=The Effect upon the White Rat of Continued Bodily Rotation |journal=The American Naturalist |volume=54 |issue=635 |pages=524–534 |jstor=2456346 |doi=10.1086/279783}} 79. ^{{cite journal |last=Griffith |first1=Coleman R. |date=December 15, 1922 |title=Are Permanent Disturbances of Equilibration Inherited? |journal=Science |volume=56 |issue=1459 |pages=676–678 |doi=10.1126/science.56.1459.676 |pmid=17778266|bibcode=1922Sci....56..676G }} 80. ^{{cite journal |last=Detlefsen |first=John A. |year=1923 |title=Are the Effects of Long-Continued Rotation in Rats Inherited? |journal=Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society |volume=62 |issue=5 |pages=292–300 |jstor=984462}} 81. ^{{cite journal |last=Detlefsen |first=John A. |date=April 1925 |title=The inheritance of acquired characters |url=http://physrev.physiology.org/content/5/2/244.extract |journal=Physiological Reviews |volume=5 |number=2 |pages=224–278}} 82. ^{{cite journal |last=Dorcus |first=Roy M. |date=June 1933 |title=The effect of intermittent rotation on orientation and the habituation of nystagmus in the rat, and some observations on the effects of pre-natal rotation on post-natal development |journal=Journal of Comparative Psychology |volume=15 |issue=3 |pages=469–475 |doi=10.1037/h0074715}} 83. ^{{harvnb|Otho S. A. Sprague Memorial Institute|1940|p=162}} 84. ^{{cite journal |last=Jollos |first=Victor |authorlink=:pl:Victor Jollos |date=September 1934 |title=Inherited changes produced by heat-treatment in Drosophila melanogaster |journal=Genetica |volume=16 |issue=5–6 |pages=476–494 |doi=10.1007/BF01984742}} 85. ^{{harvnb|Harwood|1993|pp=121–131}} 86. ^{{harvnb|Wood|2013}} 87. ^{{harvnb|Cannon|1975}} 88. ^{{harvnb|Boesiger|1974|p=29}} 89. ^{{cite journal |last=Loison |first=Laurent |date=November 2011 |title=French Roots of French Neo-Lamarckisms, 1879–1985 |journal=Journal of the History of Biology |volume=44 |issue=4 |pages=713–744 |doi=10.1007/s10739-010-9240-x |pmid=20665089}} 90. ^{{cite journal |last=Pearson |first=Roy Douglas |date=March 1988 |title=Reviews |journal=Acta Biotheoretica |type=Book review |volume=37 |issue=1 |pages=31–36 |doi=10.1007/BF00050806}} Book reviews of Animal Evolution in Changing Environments: With Special Reference to Abnormal Metamorphosis (1987) by Ryuichi Matsuda and The Evolution of Individuality (1987) by Leo W. Buss. 91. ^1 {{cite journal |last=Shapiro |first=Arthur M. |authorlink=Arthur Shapiro (ecologist) |year=1988 |title=Book Review: Animal Evolution in Changing Environments with Special Reference to Abnormal Metamorphosis |url=http://images.peabody.yale.edu/lepsoc/jls/1980s/1988/1988-42%282%29146-Shapiro.pdf |journal=Journal of the Lepidopterists' Society |type=Book review |volume=42 |issue=2 |pages=146–147 |accessdate=2015-12-11}} 92. ^{{harvnb|Baird|Scerri|McIntyre|2006|p=166}} 93. ^{{harvnb|Simpson|1944|p=75}} 94. ^{{harvnb|Simpson|1964|pp=14–60}} 95. ^{{harvnb|Simpson|1965|p=451}} 96. ^1 {{cite journal |last=Zirkle |first=Conway |authorlink=Conway Zirkle |date=January 1946 |title=The Early History of the Idea of the Inheritance of Acquired Characters and of Pangenesis |journal=Transactions of the American Philosophical Society |volume=35 |issue=2 |pages=91–151 |doi=10.2307/1005592 |jstor=1005592}} 97. ^{{harvnb|Medawar|1985|pp=166–169}} 98. ^{{harvnb|Gardner|1957|pp=142–143}} 99. ^{{harvnb|Mayr|1997|p=222}}: "...the recognition that DNA does not directly participate in the making of the phenotype and that the phenotype, in turn, does not control the composition of the DNA represents the ultimate invalidation of all theories involving the inheritance of acquired characters. This definitive refutation of Lamarck's theory of evolutionary causation clears the air." 100. ^{{harvnb|Bowler|2013|p=21}} 101. ^{{cite journal |last1=Roth |first1=Tania L. |last2=Lubin |first2=Farah D. |last3=Funk |first3=Adam J. |last4=Sweatt |first4=J. David |display-authors=3 |date=May 2009 |title=Lasting Epigenetic Influence of Early-Life Adversity on the BDNF Gene |journal=Biological Psychiatry |volume=65 |issue=9 |pages=760–769 |doi=10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.11.028 |pmc=3056389 |pmid=19150054}} 102. ^{{cite journal |title=Transgenerational Rescue of a Genetic Defect in Long-Term Potentiation and Memory Formation by Juvenile Enrichment |date=February 4, 2009 |last1=Arai |first1=Junko A. |author2=Shaomin Li |last3=Hartley |first3=Dean M. |last4=Feig |first4=Larry A. |display-authors=3 |journal=The Journal of Neuroscience |volume=29 |issue=5 |pages=1496–1502 |doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5057-08.2009 |pmc=3408235 |pmid=19193896}} 103. ^{{cite journal |last1=Hackett |first1=Jamie A. |last2=Sengupta |first2=Roopsha |last3=Zylicz |first3=Jan J. |last4=Murakami |first4=Kazuhiro |last5=Lee |first5=Caroline |last6=Down |first6=Thomas A. |last7=Surani |first7=M. Azim |display-authors=3 |date=January 25, 2013 |title=Germline DNA Demethylation Dynamics and Imprint Erasure Through 5-Hydroxymethylcytosine |journal=Science |volume=339 |issue=6118 |pages=448–452 |doi=10.1126/science.1229277 |pmid=23223451|bibcode=2013Sci...339..448H |pmc=3847602 }} 104. ^{{cite journal |last1=Bonduriansky |first1=Russell |date=June 2012 |title=Rethinking heredity, again |journal=Trends in Ecology & Evolution |volume=27 |issue=6 |pages=330–336 |doi=10.1016/j.tree.2012.02.003 |pmid=22445060}} 105. ^{{cite journal |last=Skinner |first=Michael K. |authorlink=Michael Skinner (biologist) |date=May 2015 |title=Environmental Epigenetics and a Unified Theory of the Molecular Aspects of Evolution: A Neo-Lamarckian Concept that Facilitates Neo-Darwinian Evolution |journal=Genome Biology and Evolution |volume=7 |issue=5 |pages=1296–1302 |doi=10.1093/gbe/evv073 |pmc=4453068 |pmid=25917417}} 106. ^1 {{cite web |url=http://www.genomicron.evolverzone.com/2009/03/lamarck-didnt-say-it-darwin-did/ |title=Lamarck didn't say it, Darwin did |last=Gregory |first=T. Ryan |authorlink=T. Ryan Gregory |date=March 8, 2009 |website=Genomicron |type=Blog |accessdate=2015-11-04}} 107. ^{{harvnb|Wilkins|2009|pp=295–315}} 108. ^{{cite journal |last1=Burkhardt |first1=Richard W., Jr. |date=August 2013 |title=Lamarck, Evolution, and the Inheritance of Acquired Characters |journal=Genetics |volume=194 |issue=4 |pages=793–805 |doi=10.1534/genetics.113.151852 |pmc=3730912 |pmid=23908372}} 109. ^{{cite journal |last=Penny |first=David |date=June 2015 |title=Epigenetics, Darwin, and Lamarck |journal=Genome Biology and Evolution |volume=7 |issue=6 |pages=1758–1760 |doi=10.1093/gbe/evv107 |pmc=4494054 |pmid=26026157}} 110. ^{{harvnb|Jablonka|Lamb|1995}} 111. ^{{harvnb|Moore|2015}} 112. ^{{cite journal |last=Richards |first=Eric J. |date=May 2006 |title=Inherited epigenetic variation — revisiting soft inheritance |journal=Nature Reviews Genetics |volume=7 |issue=5 |pages=395–401 |doi=10.1038/nrg1834 |pmid=16534512}} 113. ^{{cite journal |last1=Nätt |first1=Daniel |last2=Lindqvist |first2=Niclas |last3=Stranneheim |first3=Henrik |last4=Lundeberg |first4=Joakim |last5=Torjesen |first5=Peter A. |last6=Jensen |first6=Per |display-authors=3 |date=July 28, 2009 |editor1-last=Pizzari |editor1-first=Tom |title=Inheritance of Acquired Behaviour Adaptations and Brain Gene Expression in Chickens |journal=PLOS ONE |volume=4 |issue=7 |page=e6405 |doi=10.1371/journal.pone.0006405 |pmc=2713434 |pmid=19636381|bibcode=2009PLoSO...4.6405N }} 114. ^{{cite journal |author1=Sheau-Fang Ng |last2=Lin |first2=Ruby C. Y. |last3=Laybutt |first3=D. Ross |last4=Barres |first4=Romain |last5=Owens |first5=Julie A. |last6=Morris |first6=Margaret J. |display-authors=3 |date=October 21, 2010 |title=Chronic high-fat diet in fathers programs β-cell dysfunction in female rat offspring |journal=Nature |volume=467 |issue=7318 |pages=963–966 |doi=10.1038/nature09491 |pmid=20962845 |bibcode=2010Natur.467..963N }} 115. ^{{cite press release |last=Gibson |first=Andrea |date=June 16, 2013 |title=Obese male mice father offspring with higher levels of body fat |url=https://www.ohio.edu/research/communications/obese_paternal.cfm |publisher=Ohio University |accessdate=2015-11-02}} 116. ^{{cite journal |last1=Lumey |first1=Lambert H. |last2=Stein |first2=Aryeh D. |last3=Ravelli |first3=Anita C. J. |date=July 1995 |title=Timing of prenatal starvation in women and birth weight in their first and second born offspring: The Dutch famine birth cohort study |journal=European Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology and Reproductive Biology |volume=61 |issue=1 |pages=23–30 |doi=10.1016/0028-2243(95)02149-M |id={{INIST|3596539}}}} 117. ^{{cite journal |last1=Akimoto |first1=Keiko |last2=Katakami |first2=Hatsue |author3=Hyun-Jung Kim |last4=Ogawa |first4=Emiko |last5=Sano |first5=Cecile M. |last6=Wada |first6=Yuko |last7=Sano |first7=Hiroshi |display-authors=3 |date=August 2007 |title=Epigenetic Inheritance in Rice Plants |journal=Annals of Botany |volume=100 |issue=2 |pages=205–217 |doi=10.1093/aob/mcm110 |pmc=2735323 |pmid=17576658}} 118. ^{{cite journal |last=Sano |first=Hiroshi |title=Inheritance of acquired traits in plants: Reinstatement of Lamarck |date=April 2010 |journal=Plant Signaling & Behavior |volume=5 |issue=4 |pages=346–348 |doi=10.4161/psb.5.4.10803 |pmc=2958583 |pmid=20118668}} 119. ^{{cite journal |last=Singer |first=Emily |date=February 4, 2009 |title=A Comeback for Lamarckian Evolution? |url=http://www.technologyreview.com/news/411880/a-comeback-for-lamarckian-evolution/ |journal=MIT Technology Review |type=Biomedicine news}} 120. ^{{cite journal |last1=Rechavi |first1=Oded |last2=Minevich |first2=Gregory |last3=Hobert |first3=Oliver |title=Transgenerational Inheritance of an Acquired Small RNA-Based Antiviral Response in C. Elegans |date=December 9, 2011 |journal=Cell |volume=147 |issue=6 |pages=1248–1256 |doi=10.1016/j.cell.2011.10.042 |pmc=3250924 |pmid=22119442}} 121. ^{{cite journal |last1=Rechavi |first1=O. |last2=Houri-Ze'evi |first2=L. |last3=Anava |first3=S. |last4=Goh |first4=W.S. |last5=Kerk |first5=S.Y. |last6=Hannon |first6=G.J. |last7=Hobert |first7=O. |title=Starvation-induced transgenerational inheritance of small RNAs in C. elegans |journal=Cell |date=17 July 2014 |volume=158 |issue=2 |pages=277–287 |pmid=25018105 |doi=10.1016/j.cell.2014.06.020 |pmc=4377509}} 122. ^{{cite journal |last1=Handel |first1=Adam E. |last2=Ramagopalan |first2=Sreeram V. |date=May 13, 2010 |title=Is Lamarckian evolution relevant to medicine? |journal=BMC Medical Genetics |volume=11 |page=73 |doi=10.1186/1471-2350-11-73 |pmc=2876149 |pmid=20465829}} 123. ^1 {{harvnb|Springer|Holley|2013|p=94}} 124. ^{{cite journal |last1=Koonin |first1=Eugene V. |authorlink1=Eugene Koonin |last2=Wolf |first2=Yuri I. |date=November 11, 2009 |title=Is evolution Darwinian or/and Lamarckian? |journal=Biology Direct |volume=4 |page=42 |doi=10.1186/1745-6150-4-42 |pmc=2781790 |pmid=19906303}} 125. ^{{cite journal |last=Koonin |first=Eugene V. |authorlink=Eugene Koonin |date=February 2019 |title=CRISPR: a new principle of genome engineering linked to conceptual shifts in evolutionary biology |journal=Biology & Philosophy |volume=34 |issue=9 |doi=10.1007/s10539-018-9658-7}} 126. ^{{cite web |url=https://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2010/10/24/epigenetics-the-light-and-the-way/ |title=Epigenetics: the light and the way? |last=Coyne |first=Jerry |authorlink=Jerry Coyne |date=October 24, 2010 |website=Why Evolution Is True |type=Blog |accessdate=2015-11-04}} 127. ^{{cite web |url=https://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2013/09/23/epigenetics-smackdown-at-the-guardian/ |title=Epigenetics smackdown at the Guardian |last=Coyne |first=Jerry |date=September 23, 2013 |website=Why Evolution is True |type=Blog |accessdate=2015-11-04}} 128. ^González-Recio O, Toro MA, Bach A. (2015). [https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4585102/ Past, present, and future of epigenetics applied to livestock breeding]. Front Genet 6: 305. 129. ^Varona L, Munilla S, Mouresan EF, González-Rodríguez A, Moreno C, Altarriba J. (2015). A Bayesian model for the analysis of transgenerational epigenetic variation. G3: Genes, Genomes, Genetics 5(4): 477-485. 130. ^{{cite journal |last=Haig |first=David |authorlink=David Haig (biologist) |date=June 2007 |title=Weismann Rules! OK? Epigenetics and the Lamarckian temptation |journal=Biology and Philosophy |volume=22 |issue=3 |pages=415–428 |doi=10.1007/s10539-006-9033-y |quote=Modern neo-Darwinists do not deny that epigenetic mechanisms play an important role during development nor do they deny that these mechanisms enable a variety of adaptive responses to the environment. Recurrent, predictable changes of epigenetic state provide a useful set of switches that allow genetically-identical cells to acquire differentiated functions and allow facultative responses of a genotype to environmental changes (provided that 'similar' changes have occurred repeatedly in the past). However, most neo-Darwinists would claim that the ability to adaptively switch epigenetic state is a property of the DNA sequence (in the sense that alternative sequences would show different switching behavior) and that any increase of adaptedness in the system has come about by a process of natural selection.}} 131. ^{{cite journal |last=Haig |first=David |date=November 2011 |title=Lamarck Ascending! |journal=Philosophy & Theory in Biology |type=Book essay |volume=3 |issue=e204 |doi=10.3998/ptb.6959004.0003.004}} "A Review of Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology, edited by Snait B. Gissis and Eva Jablonka, MIT Press, 2011" 132. ^{{cite journal |last1=Dickins |first1=Thomas E. |last2=Rahman |first2=Qazi |date=August 7, 2012 |title=The extended evolutionary synthesis and the role of soft inheritance in evolution |journal=Proceedings of the Royal Society B |volume=279 |issue=1740 |pages=2913–2921 |doi=10.1098/rspb.2012.0273 |pmc=3385474 |pmid=22593110}} 133. ^{{cite journal |last=Whitelaw |first=Emma |authorlink=Emma Whitelaw |date=March 27, 2015 |title=Disputing Lamarckian Epigenetic Inheritance in Mammals |journal=Genome Biology |volume=16 |issue=60 |pages=60 |doi=10.1186/s13059-015-0626-0 |pmc=4375926 |pmid=25853737}} 134. ^{{cite journal |last=Weiss |first=Adam |date=October 2015 |title=Lamarckian Illusions |journal=Trends in Ecology & Evolution |volume=30 |issue=10 |pages=566–568 |doi=10.1016/j.tree.2015.08.003 |pmid=26411613}} 135. ^{{cite journal |last1=Steele |first1=E.J. |title=Somatic hypermutation in immunity and cancer: Critical analysis of strand-biased and codon-context mutation signatures |year=2016 |journal=DNA Repair |volume=45|pages=1–24 |doi=10.1016/j.dnarep.2016.07.001 |pmid=27449479}} 136. ^{{cite journal |last1=Steele |first=E.J. |last2=Pollard |first2=J.W. |year=1987 |title=Hypothesis : Somatic Hypermutation by gene conversion via the error prone DNA-to-RNA-to-DNA information loop |journal=Molecular Immunology |volume=24 |issue=6 |pages=667–673 |doi=10.1016/j.dnarep.2016.07.001 |pmid=2443841}} 137. ^1 {{Cite book |title=Somatic selection and adaptive evolution : on the inheritance of acquired characters |last=Steele |first=E. J. |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1981 |isbn= |edition=2nd}} 138. ^1 {{Cite journal |last=Steele |first=E.J.|year=2016|title=Somatic hypermutation in immunity and cancer: Critical analysis of strand-biased and codon-context mutation signatures.|url=|journal=DNA Repair |volume=45 |issue=2016 |pages=1–2 4|doi=10.1016/j.dnarep.2016.07.001 |pmid=27449479}} 139. ^{{harvnb|Steele|Lindley|Blanden|1998}} 140. ^1 2 3 {{Cite book|title=Evolution: The History of an Idea |last=Bowler, Peter J. |first=Peter J. |publisher=University of California Press |year=1989 |origyear=1983 |edition=Revised |isbn=978-0520063860 |pages=179, 341}} 141. ^{{cite journal |last1=Rosenberg |first1=Eugene |authorlink1=Eugene Rosenberg |last2=Sharon |first2=Gill |last3=Zilber-Rosenberg |first3=Ilana |date=December 2009 |title=The hologenome theory of evolution contains Lamarckian aspects within a Darwinian framework |journal=Environmental Microbiology |volume=11 |issue=12 |pages=2959–2962 |doi=10.1111/j.1462-2920.2009.01995.x |pmid=19573132}} 142. ^1 {{cite journal | last=Moran | first=Nancy A. | authorlink=Nancy A. Moran | last2=Sloan | first2=Daniel B. | title=The Hologenome Concept: Helpful or Hollow? | journal=PLOS Biology | volume=13 | issue=12 | date=2015-12-04 | doi=10.1371/journal.pbio.1002311 | pmid=26636661 | pmc=4670207 | page=e1002311}} 143. ^Depew, David J. (2003), "Baldwin Boosters, Baldwin Skeptics" in: {{cite book |title=Evolution and learning: The Baldwin effect reconsidered |last=Weber |first=Bruce H. |first2=David J. |last2=Depew |year=2003 |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-23229-6 |pages=3–31 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yBtRzBilw1MC&pg=PR9&dq=baldwin+effect#v=onepage&q&f=false }} 144. ^{{cite journal |title=The Baldwin effect |authorlink=George Gaylord Simpson |author=Simpson, George Gaylord |year=1953 |journal=Evolution |volume=7 | issue=2 |pages=110–117 |doi=10.2307/2405746|jstor=2405746 }} 145. ^Dennett, Daniel (2003), "The Baldwin Effect, a Crane, not a Skyhook" in: {{cite book |title=Evolution and learning: The Baldwin effect reconsidered |last=Weber |first=Bruce H. |first2=David J. |last2=Depew |year=2003 |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-23229-6 |pages=69–106 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yBtRzBilw1MC&pg=PR9&dq=baldwin+effect#v=onepage&q&f=false}} 146. ^{{harvnb|Cullen|2000|pp=31–60}} 147. ^{{cite journal | last=Jin | first=Xiaoxing | title=Translation and transmutation: the Origin of Species in China | journal=The British Journal for the History of Science | volume=52 | issue=1 | date=2018 | doi=10.1017/s0007087418000808 | pages=117–141}} Bibliography{{Refbegin|30em}}
Further reading{{Refbegin|30em}}
External links{{Wikipedia books|Evolution}}
4 : Non-Darwinian evolution|History of evolutionary biology|Biology theories|Jean-Baptiste Lamarck |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。