词条 | Semiorder |
释义 |
In order theory, a branch of mathematics, a semiorder is a type of ordering that may be determined for a set of items with numerical scores by declaring two items to be incomparable when their scores are within a given margin of error of each other, and by using the numerical comparison of their scores when those scores are sufficiently far apart. Semiorders were introduced and applied in mathematical psychology by {{harvtxt|Luce|1956}} as a model of human preference without the assumption that indifference is transitive. They generalize strict weak orderings, form a special case of partial orders and interval orders, and can be characterized among the partial orders by two forbidden four-item suborders. DefinitionLet X be a set of items, and let < be a binary relation on X. Items x and y are said to be incomparable, written here as x ~ y, if neither x < y nor y < x is true. Then the pair (X,<) is a semiorder if it satisfies the following three axioms:[1]
It follows from the first axiom that x ~ x, and therefore the second axiom (with y = z) implies that < is a transitive relation. One may define a partial order (X,≤) from a semiorder (X,<) by declaring that {{nowrap|x ≤ y}} whenever either {{nowrap|x < y}} or {{nowrap|1=x = y}}. Of the axioms that a partial order is required to obey, reflexivity follows automatically from this definition, antisymmetry follows from the first semiorder axiom, and transitivity follows from the second semiorder axiom. Conversely, from a partial order defined in this way, the semiorder may be recovered by declaring that {{nowrap|x < y}} whenever {{nowrap|x ≤ y}} and {{nowrap|x ≠ y}}. The first of the semiorder axioms listed above follows automatically from the axioms defining a partial order, but the others do not. The second and third semiorder axioms forbid partial orders of four items forming two disjoint chains: the second axiom forbids two chains of two items each, while the third item forbids a three-item chain with one unrelated item. PropertiesEvery strict weak ordering < is also a semi-order. More particularly, transitivity of < and transitivity of incomparability with respect to < together imply the above axiom 2, while transitivity of incomparability alone implies axiom 3. The semiorder shown in the top image is not a strict weak ordering, since the rightmost vertice is incomparable to its two closest left neighbors, but they are comparable. A relation is a semiorder if, and only if, it can be obtained as an interval order of unit length intervals . According to Amartya K. Sen,[2] semi-orders were examined by Dean T. Jamison and Lawrence J. Lau[3] and found to be a special case of quasitransitive relations. In fact, every semiorder is a quasitransitive relation, since it is a transitive one. Moreover, adding to a given semiorder all its pairs of incomparable items keeps the resulting relation a quasitransitive one.[4] Utility theoryThe original motivation for introducing semiorders was to model human preferences without assuming (as strict weak orderings do) that incomparability is a transitive relation. For instance, if x, y, and z represent three quantities of the same material, and x and z differ by the smallest amount that is perceptible as a difference, while y is halfway between the two of them, then it is reasonable for a preference to exist between x and z but not between the other two pairs, violating transitivity.[5] Thus, suppose that X is a set of items, and u is a utility function that maps the members of X to real numbers. A strict weak ordering can be defined on x by declaring two items to be incomparable when they have equal utilities, and otherwise using the numerical comparison, but this necessarily leads to a transitive incomparability relation. Instead, if one sets a numerical threshold (which may be normalized to 1) such that utilities within that threshold of each other are declared incomparable, then a semiorder arises. Specifically, define a binary relation < from X and u by setting x < y whenever u(x) ≤ u(y) − 1. Then (X,<) is a semiorder.[6] It may equivalently be defined as the interval order defined by the intervals [u(x),u(x) + 1].[7] In the other direction, not every semiorder can be defined from numerical utilities in this way. For instance, if a semiorder (X,<) includes an uncountable totally ordered subset then there do not exist sufficiently many sufficiently well-spaced real-numbers to represent this subset numerically. However, every finite semiorder can be defined from a utility function.[8] {{harvtxt|Fishburn|1973}} supplies a precise characterization of the semiorders that may be defined numerically. Other resultsThe number of distinct semiorders on n unlabeled items is given by the Catalan numbers [9] while the number of semiorders on n labeled items is given by the sequence 1, 1, 3, 19, 183, 2371, 38703, 763099, 17648823, ... {{OEIS|A006531}}.[10] Any finite semiorder has order dimension at most three.[11] Among all partial orders with a fixed number of elements and a fixed number of comparable pairs, the partial orders that have the largest number of linear extensions are semiorders.[12] Semiorders are known to obey the 1/3–2/3 conjecture: in any finite semiorder that is not a total order, there exists a pair of elements x and y such that x appears earlier than y in between 1/3 and 2/3 of the linear extensions of the semiorder.[13] The set of semiorders on an n-element set is well-graded: if two semiorders on the same set differ from each other by the addition or removal of k order relations, then it is possible to find a path of k steps from the first semiorder to the second one, in such a way that each step of the path adds or removes a single order relation and each intermediate state in the path is itself a semiorder.[14] The incomparability graphs of semiorders are called indifference graphs, and are a special case of the interval graphs.{{sfnp|Roberts|1969}} If a semiorder is given only in terms of the order relation between its pairs of elements, then it is possible to construct a utility function that represents the order in time {{math|O(n2)}}, where {{mvar|n}} is the number of elements in the semiorder.{{sfnp|Avery|1992}} Notes1. ^{{harvtxt|Luce|1956}} describes an equivalent set of four axioms, the first two of which combine the definition of incomparability and the first axiom listed here. 2. ^{{cite journal | url=https://www.ihs.ac.at/publications/eco/visit_profs/blume/sen.pdf | author=Amartya K. Sen | title=Choice Functions and Revealed Preference | journal=The Review of Economic Studies | volume=38 | number=3 | pages=307–317 | date=Jul 1971 }} Here: Sect.10, p.314 3. ^{{cite report | url= | author=Dean T. Jamison and Lawrence J. Lau | title=Semiorders, Revealed Preference, and the Theory of the Consumer Demand | institution=Stanford University, Institute for Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences | type=Technical Report No.31 | date=Jul 1970 }} Presented at the World Economics Congress, Cambridge, Sep 1970. 4. ^{{cite report | arxiv=1806.05036v2 | author=Jochen Burghardt | title=Simple Laws about Nonprominent Properties of Binary Relations | type=Technical Report | date=Nov 2018 }} Here: Lemma 20, p.27. Since Luce modelled indifference between x and y as "neither xRy nor yRx", while Sen modelled it as "both xRy and xRy", Sen's remark on p.314 is likely to mean the latter property. 5. ^{{harvtxt|Luce|1956}}, p. 179. 6. ^{{harvtxt|Luce|1956}}, Theorem 3 describes a more general situation in which the threshold for comparability between two utilities is a function of the utility rather than being identically 1. 7. ^{{harvtxt|Fishburn|1970}}. 8. ^This result is typically credited to {{harvtxt|Scott|Suppes|1958}}; see, e.g., {{harvtxt|Rabinovitch|1977}}. However, {{harvtxt|Luce|1956}}, Theorem 2 proves a more general statement, that a finite semiorder can be defined from a utility function and a threshold function whenever a certain underlying weak order can be defined numerically. For finite semiorders, it is trivial that the weak order can be defined numerically with a unit threshold function. 9. ^{{harvtxt|Kim|Roush|1978}}. 10. ^{{harvtxt|Chandon|Lemaire|Pouget|1978}}. 11. ^{{harvtxt|Rabinovitch|1978}}. 12. ^{{harvtxt|Fishburn|Trotter|1992}}. 13. ^{{harvtxt|Brightwell|1989}}. 14. ^{{harvtxt|Doignon|Falmagne|1997}}. References
| last = Avery | first = Peter | doi = 10.1016/0196-6774(92)90010-A | issue = 1 | journal = Journal of Algorithms | mr = 1146337 | pages = 144–147 | title = An algorithmic proof that semiorders are representable | volume = 13 | year = 1992}}.
| last = Brightwell | first = Graham R. | authorlink = Graham Brightwell | doi = 10.1007/BF00353656 | issue = 4 | journal = Order | pages = 369–380 | title = Semiorders and the 1/3–2/3 conjecture | volume = 5 | year = 1989}}.
| last1 = Chandon | first1 = J.-L. | last2 = Lemaire | first2 = J. | last3 = Pouget | first3 = J. | mr = 517680 | issue = 62 | journal = Centre de Mathématique Sociale. École Pratique des Hautes Études. Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines | pages = 61–80, 83 | title = Dénombrement des quasi-ordres sur un ensemble fini | year = 1978}}.
| last1 = Doignon | first1 = Jean-Paul | last2 = Falmagne | first2 = Jean-Claude | author2-link = Jean-Claude Falmagne | doi = 10.1016/S0012-365X(96)00095-7 | mr = 1468838 | issue = 1-3 | journal = Discrete Mathematics | pages = 35–44 | title = Well-graded families of relations | volume = 173 | year = 1997}}.
| last = Fishburn | first = Peter C. | authorlink = Peter C. Fishburn | mr = 0253942 | journal = J. Mathematical Psychology | pages = 144–149 | title = Intransitive indifference with unequal indifference intervals | volume = 7 | year = 1970 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(70)90062-3}}.
| last = Fishburn | first = Peter C. | authorlink = Peter C. Fishburn | mr = 0316322 | journal = J. Mathematical Psychology | pages = 91–105 | title = Interval representations for interval orders and semiorders | volume = 10 | year = 1973 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(73)90007-2}}.
| last1 = Fishburn | first1 = Peter C. | author1-link = Peter C. Fishburn | last2 = Trotter | first2 = W. T. | doi = 10.1016/0012-365X(92)90036-F | mr = 1171114 | issue = 1 | journal = Discrete Mathematics | pages = 25–40 | title = Linear extensions of semiorders: a maximization problem | volume = 103 | year = 1992}}.
| jstor=1913813 | doi=10.2307/1913813 | last1=Jamison | first1=Dean T. | author1-link=Dean Jamison | last2=Lau | first2=Lawrence J. | author2-link=Lawrence J. Lau | title=Semiorders and the Theory of Choice | journal=Econometrica | volume=41 | number=5 | pages=901–912 | date=Sep 1973 }}.
| jstor=1911339 | doi=10.2307/1911339 | last1=Jamison | first1=Dean T. | last2=Lau | first2=Lawrence J. | title=Semiorders and the Theory of Choice: A Correction | journal=Econometrica | volume=43 | number=5–6 | pages=979–980 | date=Sep–Nov 1975 }}.
| jstor=1913952 | doi=10.2307/1913952 | last1=Jamison | first1=Dean T. | last2=Lau | first2=Lawrence J. | title=The Nature of Equilibrium with Semiordered Preferences | journal=Econometrica | volume=45 | number=7 | pages=1595–1605 | date=Oct 1977 }}.
| last1 = Kim | first1 = K. H. | last2 = Roush | first2 = F. W. | mr = 538212 | issue = 2 | journal = Journal of Combinatorics, Information &System Sciences | pages = 58–61 | title = Enumeration of isomorphism classes of semiorders | volume = 3 | year = 1978}}.
| last = Luce | first = R. Duncan | authorlink = R. Duncan Luce | mr = 0078632 | journal = Econometrica | pages = 178–191 | title = Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination | jstor = 1905751 | volume = 24 | year = 1956 | url = https://www.imbs.uci.edu/files/personnel/luce/pre1990/1956/Luce_Econometrica_1956.pdf | doi=10.2307/1905751}}.
| last = Rabinovitch | first = Issie | mr = 0437404 | issue = 2 | journal = J. Mathematical Psychology | pages = 209–212 | title = The Scott-Suppes theorem on semiorders | volume = 15 | year = 1977 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(77)90030-x}}.
| last = Rabinovitch | first = Issie | mr = 0498294 | issue = 1 | journal = Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A | pages = 50–61 | title = The dimension of semiorders | volume = 25 | year = 1978 | doi=10.1016/0097-3165(78)90030-4}}.
| last = Roberts | first = Fred S. | authorlink = Fred S. Roberts | contribution = Indifference graphs | mr = 0252267 | pages = 139–146 | publisher = Academic Press, New York | title = Proof Techniques in Graph Theory (Proc. Second Ann Arbor Graph Theory Conf., Ann Arbor, Mich., 1968) | year = 1969}}.
| last1 = Scott | first1 = Dana | author1-link = Dana Scott | last2 = Suppes | first2 = Patrick | author2-link = Patrick Suppes | mr = 0115919 | journal = The Journal of Symbolic Logic | pages = 113–128 | title = Foundational aspects of theories of measurement | volume = 23 | year = 1958 | doi=10.2307/2964389}}. Further reading
| last1 = Pirlot | first1 = M. | last2 = Vincke | first2 = Ph. | mr = 1472236 | isbn = 0-7923-4617-3 | location = Dordrecht | publisher = Kluwer Academic Publishers Group | series = Theory and Decision Library. Series B: Mathematical and Statistical Methods | title = Semiorders: Properties, representations, applications | volume = 36 | year = 1997}}. 2 : Order theory|Binary relations |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。