词条 | Medical ethics |
释义 |
}}Medical ethics is a system of moral principles that apply values to the practice of clinical medicine and in scientific research. Medical ethics is based on a set of values that professionals can refer to in the case of any confusion or conflict. These values include the respect for autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence, and justice.[1] Such tenets may allow doctors, care providers, and families to create a treatment plan and work towards the same common goal.[2] It is important to note that these four values are not ranked in order of importance or relevance and that they all encompass values pertaining to medical ethics. [3] However, a conflict may arise leading to the need for hierarchy in an ethical system, such that some moral obligations overrule others with the purpose of applying the best moral judgement to a difficult medical situation.[4] There are several codes of conduct. The Hippocratic Oath discusses basic principles for medical professionals.[4] This document dates back to the fifth century BCE.[5] Both The Declaration of Helsinki (1964) and The Nuremberg Code (1947) are two well-known and well respected documents contributing to medical ethics. Other important markings in the history of Medical Ethics include Roe v. Wade in 1973 and the development of Hemodialysis in the 1960s. More recently, CRISPR/Cas9, a new technique for gene editing aiming at treating, preventing and curing diseases utilizing gene editing, is raising important moral questions about its applications in medicine and treatments as well as societal impacts on future generations. [6][7] As this field continues to develop and change throughout history, the focus remains on fair, balanced, and moral thinking. Medical ethics encompasses a practical application in clinical settings as well as scholarly work on its history, philosophy, and sociology. History{{See also|List of medical ethics cases}}The term medical ethics first dates back to 1803, when English author and physician Thomas Percival published a document describing the requirements and expectations of medical professionals within medical facilities. The Code of Ethics was then adapted in 1847, relying heavily on Percival's words.[8] Over the years in 1903, 1912, and 1947, revisions have been made to the original document.[8] The practice of Medical Ethics is widely accepted and practiced throughout the world.[3] Historically, Western medical ethics may be traced to guidelines on the duty of physicians in antiquity, such as the Hippocratic Oath, and early Christian teachings. The first code of medical ethics, Formula Comitis Archiatrorum, was published in the 5th century, during the reign of the Ostrogothic king Theodoric the Great. In the medieval and early modern period, the field is indebted to Islamic scholarship such as Ishaq ibn Ali al-Ruhawi (who wrote the Conduct of a Physician, the first book dedicated to medical ethics), Avicenna's Canon of Medicine and Muhammad ibn Zakariya ar-Razi (known as Rhazes in the West), Jewish thinkers such as Maimonides, Roman Catholic scholastic thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas, and the case-oriented analysis (casuistry) of Catholic moral theology. These intellectual traditions continue in Catholic, Islamic and Jewish medical ethics. By the 18th and 19th centuries, medical ethics emerged as a more self-conscious discourse. In England, Thomas Percival, a physician and author, crafted the first modern code of medical ethics. He drew up a pamphlet with the code in 1794 and wrote an expanded version in 1803, in which he coined the expressions "medical ethics" and "medical jurisprudence".[9] However, there are some who see Percival's guidelines that relate to physician consultations as being excessively protective of the home physician's reputation. Jeffrey Berlant is one such critic who considers Percival's codes of physician consultations as being an early example of the anti-competitive, "guild"-like nature of the physician community.[10][11] In 1815, the Apothecaries Act was passed by the Parliament of the United Kingdom. It introduced compulsory apprenticeship and formal qualifications for the apothecaries of the day under the license of the Society of Apothecaries. This was the beginning of regulation of the medical profession in the UK. In 1847, the American Medical Association adopted its first code of ethics, with this being based in large part upon Percival's work.[12] While the secularized field borrowed largely from Catholic medical ethics, in the 20th century a distinctively liberal Protestant approach was articulated by thinkers such as Joseph Fletcher. In the 1960s and 1970s, building upon liberal theory and procedural justice, much of the discourse of medical ethics went through a dramatic shift and largely reconfigured itself into bioethics.[13] Well-known medical ethics cases include:
Since the 1970s, the growing influence of ethics in contemporary medicine can be seen in the increasing use of Institutional Review Boards to evaluate experiments on human subjects, the establishment of hospital ethics committees, the expansion of the role of clinician ethicists, and the integration of ethics into many medical school curricula.[14] ValuesA common framework used in the analysis of medical ethics is the "four principles" approach postulated by Tom Beauchamp and James Childress in their textbook Principles of biomedical ethics. It recognizes four basic moral principles, which are to be judged and weighed against each other, with attention given to the scope of their application. The four principles are:[15]
AutonomyThe principle of autonomy views the rights of an individual to self-determination. This is rooted in society's respect for individuals' ability to make informed decisions about personal matters with freedom. Autonomy has become more important as social values have shifted to define medical quality in terms of outcomes that are important to the patient and their family rather than medical professionals. The increasing importance of autonomy can be seen as a social reaction against the "paternalistic" tradition within healthcare.[16] Some have questioned whether the backlash against historically excessive paternalism in favor of patient autonomy has inhibited the proper use of soft paternalism to the detriment of outcomes for some patients.[17] The definition of autonomy is the ability of an individual to make a rational, un-influenced decision. Therefore, it can be said that autonomy is a general indicator of a healthy mind and body. The progression of many terminal diseases are characterized by loss of autonomy, in various manners and extents. For example, dementia, a chronic and progressive disease that attacks the brain can induce memory loss and cause a decrease in rational thinking, almost always results in the loss of autonomy.[18] Psychiatrists and clinical psychologists are often asked to evaluate a patient's capacity for making life-and-death decisions at the end of life. Persons with a psychiatric condition such as delirium or clinical depression may lack capacity to make end-of-life decisions. For these persons, a request to refuse treatment may be taken in the context of their condition. Unless there is a clear advance directive to the contrary, persons lacking mental capacity are treated according to their best interests. This will involve an assessment involving people who know the person best to what decisions the person would have made had they not lost capacity.[19] Persons with the mental capacity to make end-of-life decisions may refuse treatment with the understanding that it may shorten their life. Psychiatrists and psychologists may be involved to support decision making.[20] BeneficenceThe term beneficence refers to actions that promote the well being of others. In the medical context, this means taking actions that serve the best interests of patients and their families. However, uncertainty surrounds the precise definition of which practices do in fact help patients. James Childress and Tom Beauchamp in Principle of Biomedical Ethics (1978) identify beneficence as one of the core values of healthcare ethics. Some scholars, such as Edmund Pellegrino, argue that beneficence is the only fundamental principle of medical ethics. They argue that healing should be the sole purpose of medicine, and that endeavors like cosmetic surgery and euthanasia are severely unethical and against the Hippocratic Oath.it is one of the most important principles. Non-maleficence{{Main|Primum non nocere}}The concept of non-maleficence is embodied by the phrase, "first, do no harm," or the Latin, primum non nocere. Many consider that should be the main or primary consideration (hence primum): that it is more important not to harm your patient, than to do them good, which is part of the hippocratic oath that doctors take.[21] This is partly because enthusiastic practitioners are prone to using treatments that they believe will do good, without first having evaluated them adequately to ensure they do no harm to the patient. Much harm has been done to patients as a result, as in the saying, "The treatment was a success, but the patient died." It is not only more important to do no harm than to do good; it is also important to know how likely it is that your treatment will harm a patient. So a physician should go further than not prescribing medications they know to be harmful—he or she should not prescribe medications (or otherwise treat the patient) unless s/he knows that the treatment is unlikely to be harmful; or at the very least, that patient understands the risks and benefits, and that the likely benefits outweigh the likely risks. In practice, however, many treatments carry some risk of harm. In some circumstances, e.g. in desperate situations where the outcome without treatment will be grave, risky treatments that stand a high chance of harming the patient will be justified, as the risk of not treating is also very likely to do harm. So the principle of non-maleficence is not absolute, and balances against the principle of beneficence (doing good), as the effects of the two principles together often give rise to a double effect (further described in next section). Even basic actions like taking a blood sample or an injection of a drug cause harm to the patient's body. Euthanasia also goes against the principle of beneficence because the patient dies as a result of the medical treatment by the doctor. Double effect{{Main|Principle of double effect}}Double effect refers to two types of consequences that may be produced by a single action,[22] and in medical ethics it is usually regarded as the combined effect of beneficence and non-maleficence.[23]A commonly cited example of this phenomenon is the use of morphine or other analgesic in the dying patient. Such use of morphine can have the beneficial effect of easing the pain and suffering of the patient while simultaneously having the maleficent effect of shortening the life of the patient through the deactivation of the respiratory system.[24] Respect for human rightsThe human rights era started with the formation of the United Nations in 1945, which was charged with the promotion of human rights. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948) was the first major document to define human rights. Medical doctors have an ethical duty to protect the human rights and human dignity of the patient so the advent of a document that defines human rights has had its effect on medical ethics.[25] Most codes of medical ethics now require respect for the human rights of the patient. The Council of Europe promotes the rule of law and observance of human rights in Europe. The Council of Europe adopted the European Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine (1997) to create a uniform code of medical ethics for its 47 member-states. The Convention applies international human rights law to medical ethics. It provides special protection of physical integrity for those who are unable to consent, which includes children.
As of December 2013, the Convention had been ratified or acceded to by twenty-nine member-states of the Council of Europe.[27] The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) also promotes the protection of human rights and human dignity. According to UNESCO, "Declarations are another means of defining norms, which are not subject to ratification. Like recommendations, they set forth universal principles to which the community of States wished to attribute the greatest possible authority and to afford the broadest possible support." UNESCO adopted the Universal Declaration on Human Rights and Biomedicine to advance the application of international human rights law in medical ethics. The Declaration provides special protection of human rights for incompetent persons.
ConflictsBetween autonomy and beneficence/non-maleficenceAutonomy can come into conflict with beneficence when patients disagree with recommendations that healthcare professionals believe are in the patient's best interest. When the patient's interests conflict with the patient's welfare, different societies settle the conflict in a wide range of manners. In general, Western medicine defers to the wishes of a mentally competent patient to make their own decisions, even in cases where the medical team believes that they are not acting in their own best interests. However, many other societies prioritize beneficence over autonomy. Examples include when a patient does not want a treatment because of, for example, religious or cultural views. In the case of euthanasia, the patient, or relatives of a patient, may want to end the life of the patient. Also, the patient may want an unnecessary treatment, as can be the case in hypochondria or with cosmetic surgery; here, the practitioner may be required to balance the desires of the patient for medically unnecessary potential risks against the patient's informed autonomy in the issue. A doctor may want to prefer autonomy because refusal to please the patient's self-determination would harm the doctor-patient relationship. Individuals' capacity for informed decision-making may come into question during resolution of conflicts between autonomy and beneficence. The role of surrogate medical decision makers is an extension of the principle of autonomy. On the other hand, autonomy and beneficence/non-maleficence may also overlap. For example, a breach of patients' autonomy may cause decreased confidence for medical services in the population and subsequently less willingness to seek help, which in turn may cause inability to perform beneficence. The principles of autonomy and beneficence/non-maleficence may also be expanded to include effects on the relatives of patients or even the medical practitioners, the overall population and economic issues when making medical decisions. Euthanasia{{Main|Euthanasia}}There is disagreement among American physicians as to whether the non-maleficence principle excludes the practice of euthanasia. Euthanasia is currently legal in the states of Washington DC, California, Colorado, Oregon, Vermont, and Washington. Around the world, there are different organizations that campaign to change legislation about the issue of physician-assisted death, or PAD. Examples of such organizations are the Hemlock Society of the United States and the Dignity in Dying campaign in the United Kingdom. These groups believe that doctors should be given the right to end a patient's life only if the patient is conscious enough to decide for themselves, is knowledgeable about the possibility of alternative care, and has willingly asked to end their life or requested access to the means to do so. This argument is disputed in other parts of the world. For example, in the state of Louisiana, giving advice or supplying the means to end a person's life is considered a criminal act and can be charged as a felony. In state courts, this crime is comparable to manslaughter. The same laws apply in the states of Mississippi and Nebraska.[29] Informed consent{{Main|Informed consent}}{{more citations needed|section|date=November 2018}}Informed consent in ethics usually refers to the idea that a person must be fully informed about and understand the potential benefits and risks of their choice of treatment. A correlate to "informed consent" is the concept of informed refusal. An uninformed person is at risk of mistakenly making a choice not reflective of his or her values or wishes. It does not specifically mean the process of obtaining consent, or the specific legal requirements, which vary from place to place, for capacity to consent. Patients can elect to make their own medical decisions or can delegate decision-making authority to another party. If the patient is incapacitated, laws around the world designate different processes for obtaining informed consent, typically by having a person appointed by the patient or their next of kin make decisions for them. The value of informed consent is closely related to the values of autonomy and truth telling. Confidentiality{{Further|Confidentiality}}Confidentiality is commonly applied to conversations between doctors and patients. This concept is commonly known as patient-physician privilege. Legal protections prevent physicians from revealing their discussions with patients, even under oath in court. Confidentiality is mandated in America by the Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act of 1996[30] known as HIPAA , specifically the Privacy Rule, and various state laws, some more rigorous than HIPAA. However, numerous exceptions to the rules have been carved out over the years. For example, many states require physicians to report gunshot wounds to the police and impaired drivers to the Department of Motor Vehicles. Confidentiality is also challenged in cases involving the diagnosis of a sexually transmitted disease in a patient who refuses to reveal the diagnosis to a spouse, and in the termination of a pregnancy in an underage patient, without the knowledge of the patient's parents. Many states in the U.S. have laws governing parental notification in underage abortion.[31][32] Traditionally, medical ethics has viewed the duty of confidentiality as a relatively non-negotiable tenet of medical practice. More recently, critics like Jacob Appel have argued for a more nuanced approach to the duty that acknowledges the need for flexibility in many cases.[33] Confidentiality is an important issue in primary care ethics, where physicians care for many patients from the same family and community, and where third parties often request information from the considerable medical database typically gathered in primary health care. Healthcare practice and privacy in an Online WorldIn increasing frequency, medical researchers are researching activities in online environments such as discussion boards and bulletin boards, and there is concern that the requirements of informed consent and privacy are not applied, although some guidelines do exist.[34] One issue that has arisen, however, is the disclosure of information. While researchers wish to quote from the original source in order to argue a point, this can have repercussions when the identity of the patient is not kept confidential. The quotations and other information about the site can be used to identify the patient, and researchers have reported cases where members of the site, bloggers and others have used this information as 'clues' in a game in an attempt to identify the site.[35] Some researchers have employed various methods of "heavy disguise."[35] including discussing a different condition from that under study.[36][37] Healthcare institutions' websites have the responsibility to ensure that the private medical records of their online visitors are secure from being marketed and monetized into the hands of drug companies, occupation records, and insurance companies. The delivery of diagnosis online leads patients to believe that doctors in some parts of the country are at the direct service of drug companies, finding diagnosis as convenient as what drug still has patent rights on it.[38] Physicians and drug companies are found to be competing for top ten search engine ranks to lower costs of selling these drugs with little to no patient involvement.[39] ]With the expansion of internet healthcare platforms, online practitioner legitimacy and privacy accountability face unique challenges such as e-paparazzi, online information brokers, industrial spies, unlicensed information providers that work outside of traditional medical codes for profit. The American Medical Association (AMA) states that medical websites have the responsibility to ensure the health care privacy of online visitors and protect patient records from being marketed and monetized into the hands of insurance companies, employers, and marketers. [40]With the rapid unification of healthcare, business practices, computer science and e-commerce to create these online diagnostic websites, efforts to maintain health care system's ethical confidentiality standard need to keep up as well. Over the next few years, the Department of Health and Human Services have stated that they will be working towards lawfully protecting the online privacy and digital transfers of patient Electronic Medical Records (EMR) under The Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act (HIPAA). [41] Control and resolutionTo ensure that appropriate ethical values are being applied within hospitals, effective hospital accreditation requires that ethical considerations are taken into account, for example with respect to physician integrity, conflict of interest, research ethics and organ transplantation ethics. GuidelinesThere is much documentation of the history and necessity of the Declaration of Helsinki. The first code of conduct for research including medical ethics was the Nuremberg Code. This document had large ties to Nazi war crimes, as it was introduced in 1947, so it didn't make much of a difference in terms of regulating practice. This issue called for the creation of the Declaration. There are some stark differences between the Nuremberg Code and the Declaration of Helsinki, including the way it is written. Nuremberg was written in a very concise manner, with a simple explanation. The Declaration of Helsinki is written with a thorough explanation in mind and including many specific commentaries.[40] In the United Kingdom, General Medical Council provides clear overall modern guidance in the form of its 'Good Medical Practice' statement.[41] Other organizations, such as the Medical Protection Society and a number of university departments, are often consulted by British doctors regarding issues relating to ethics. Ethics committeesOften, simple communication is not enough to resolve a conflict, and a hospital ethics committee must convene to decide a complex matter. These bodies are composed primarily of healthcare professionals, but may also include philosophers, lay people, and clergy – indeed, in many parts of the world their presence is considered mandatory in order to provide balance. With respect to the expected composition of such bodies in the US, Europe and Australia, the following applies.[42]
The assignment of philosophers or religious clerics will reflect the importance attached by the society to the basic values involved. An example from Sweden with Torbjörn Tännsjö on a couple of such committees indicates secular trends gaining influence. Cultural concernsCulture differences can create difficult medical ethics problems. Some cultures have spiritual or magical theories about the origins and cause of disease, for example, and reconciling these beliefs with the tenets of Western medicine can be very difficult. Humanitarian medical volunteerismOne concern regarding the intersection of medical ethics and humanitarian medical aid is how such assistance can be as harmful as it is helpful to the community being served. One such example being how political forces may control how foreign humanitarian aid can be utilized in the region it is meant to be provided in. This would be congruous in situations where political strife could lead such aid being used in favor of one group over another. Another example of how foreign humanitarian aid can be misused in its intended community includes the possibility of dissonance forming between a foreign humanitarian aid group and the community being served.[43] Examples of this could include the relationships being viewed between aid workers, style of dress, or the lack of education regarding local culture and customs.[44] Conflicts of interestPhysicians should not allow a conflict of interest to influence medical judgment. In some cases, conflicts are hard to avoid, and doctors have a responsibility to avoid entering such situations. Research has shown that conflicts of interests are very common among both academic physicians[45] and physicians in practice.[46] ReferralDoctors who receive income from referring patients for medical tests have been shown to refer more patients for medical tests.[47] This practice is proscribed by the American College of Physicians Ethics Manual.[48] Fee splitting and the payments of commissions to attract referrals of patients is considered unethical and unacceptable in most parts of the world.{{citation needed|date=October 2015}} Vendor relationships{{See also|Pharmaceutical marketing#To health care providers}}Studies show that doctors can be influenced by drug company inducements, including gifts and food.[49] Industry-sponsored Continuing Medical Education (CME) programs influence prescribing patterns.[50] Many patients surveyed in one study agreed that physician gifts from drug companies influence prescribing practices.[51] A growing movement among physicians is attempting to diminish the influence of pharmaceutical industry marketing upon medical practice, as evidenced by Stanford University's ban on drug company-sponsored lunches and gifts. Other academic institutions that have banned pharmaceutical industry-sponsored gifts and food include the Johns Hopkins Medical Institutions, University of Michigan, University of Pennsylvania, and Yale University.[52][53] Treatment of family membersThe American Medical Association (AMA) states that "Physicians generally should not treat themselves or members of their immediate family".[54] This code seeks to protect patients and physicians because professional objectivity can be compromised when the physician is treating a loved one. Studies from multiple health organizations have illustrated that physician-family member relationships may cause an increase in diagnostic testing and costs.[55] Many doctors still treat their family members. Doctors who do so must be vigilant not to create conflicts of interest or treat inappropriately.[56][57] Physicians that treat family members need to be conscious of conflicting expectations and dilemmas when treating relatives, as established medical ethical principles may not be morally imperative when family members are confronted with serious illness.[55] Sexual relationshipsSexual relationships between doctors and patients can create ethical conflicts, since sexual consent may conflict with the fiduciary responsibility of the physician. Out of the many disciplines in current medicine, there are studies that have been conducted in order to ascertain the occurrence of Doctor-Patient sexual misconduct. Results from those studies appear to indicate that certain disciplines are more likely to be offenders than others. Psychiatrists and Obstetrician-Gynecologists for example, are two disciplines noted for having a higher rate of sexual misconduct.[58] The violation of ethical conduct between doctors and patients also has an association with the age and sex of doctor and patient. Male physicians aged 40–49 and 50–59 years are two groups that have been found to be more likely to have been reported for sexual misconduct, while women aged 20–39 have been found to make up a significant portion of reported victims of sexual misconduct.[59] Doctors who enter into sexual relationships with patients face the threats of losing their medical license and prosecution. In the early 1990s, it was estimated that 2-9% of doctors had violated this rule.[60] Sexual relationships between physicians and patients' relatives may also be prohibited in some jurisdictions, although this prohibition is highly controversial.[61] Futility{{Further|Futile medical care}}The concept of medical futility has been an important topic in discussions of medical ethics. What should be done if there is no chance that a patient will survive but the family members insist on advanced care? Previously, some articles defined futility as the patient having less than a one percent chance of surviving. Some of these cases are examined in court. Advance directives include living wills and durable powers of attorney for health care. (See also Do Not Resuscitate and cardiopulmonary resuscitation) In many cases, the "expressed wishes" of the patient are documented in these directives, and this provides a framework to guide family members and health care professionals in the decision-making process when the patient is incapacitated. Undocumented expressed wishes can also help guide decisions in the absence of advance directives, as in the Quinlan case in Missouri. "Substituted judgment" is the concept that a family member can give consent for treatment if the patient is unable (or unwilling) to give consent themselves. The key question for the decision-making surrogate is not, "What would you like to do?", but instead, "What do you think the patient would want in this situation?". Courts have supported family's arbitrary definitions of futility to include simple biological survival, as in the Baby K case (in which the courts ordered a child born with only a brain stem instead of a complete brain to be kept on a ventilator based on the religious belief that all life must be preserved). In some hospitals, medical futility is referred to as "non-beneficial care." Baby Doe Law establishes state protection for a disabled child's right to life, ensuring that this right is protected even over the wishes of parents or guardians in cases where they want to withhold treatment. See also{{col div|colwidth=15em}}
Reproductive medicine
Medical research{{col div|colwidth=15em}}
Sources and references1. ^{{Cite journal|last=Beauchamp|first=J.|year=2013|title=Principles of Biomedical Ethics|url=|journal=Principles of Biomedical Ethics|volume=7|pages=|via=}} 2. ^{{Cite journal|last=Weise|first=Mary|year=2016|title=Medical Ethics Made Easy|url=http://journals.lww.com/professionalcasemanagementjournal/Abstract/2016/03000/Medical_Ethics_Made_Easy.5.aspx|journal=Professional Case Management|volume=21|issue=2|pages=88–94|via=|doi=10.1097/ncm.0000000000000151|pmid=26844716|deadurl=yes|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20170401055745/http://journals.lww.com/professionalcasemanagementjournal/Abstract/2016/03000/Medical_Ethics_Made_Easy.5.aspx|archivedate=2017-04-01|access-date=2019-01-25|df=}} 3. ^1 {{cite web|url=https://depts.washington.edu/bioethx/tools/princpl.html|title=Bioethic Tools: Principles of Bioethics|website=depts.washington.edu|access-date=2017-03-21|deadurl=no|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20170510052851/http://depts.washington.edu/bioethx/tools/princpl.html|archivedate=2017-05-10|df=}} 4. ^1 {{Cite journal|last=Berdine|first=Gilbert|date=2015-01-10|title=The Hippocratic Oath and Principles of Medical Ethics|url=http://pulmonarychronicles.com/index.php/pulmonarychronicles/article/view/185|journal=The Southwest Respiratory and Critical Care Chronicles|language=en|volume=3|issue=9|pages=28–32–32|issn=2325-9205|doi=10.12746/swrccc.v3i9.185}} 5. ^{{Cite journal|last=Riddick|first=Frank|date=Spring 2003|title=The Code of Medical Ethics of the American Medical Association|pmc=3399321|journal=The Ochsner Journal|volume=5 |issue=2|pages=6–10|pmid=22826677}} 6. ^{{Cite web|url=https://login.proxylib.csueastbay.edu/login?qurl=https://www.sciencedirect.com%2fscience%2farticle%2fpii%2fS0140673617303896|title=Safeguarding the future of human gene editing.|last=|first=|date=|website=login.proxylib.csueastbay.edu|archive-url=|archive-date=|dead-url=|access-date=2019-03-19}} 7. ^{{Cite journal|last=Baylis|first=Françoise|date=2018-03-01|title=Counterpoint: The Potential Harms of Human Gene Editing Using CRISPR-Cas9|url=http://clinchem.aaccjnls.org/content/64/3/489|journal=Clinical Chemistry|language=en|volume=64|issue=3|pages=489–491|doi=10.1373/clinchem.2017.278317|issn=0009-9147|pmid=29490999}} 8. ^1 {{Cite journal|last=Riddick|first=Frank|year=2003|title=The Code of Medical Ethics of the American Medical Association|journal=The Ochsner Journal|volume=5|issue=2|pages=6–10|pmc=3399321|pmid=22826677|via=}} 9. ^Codes of Ethics: Some History, Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions at IIT {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120206204827/http://ethics.iit.edu/perspective/pers19_1fall99_2.html |date=2012-02-06 }} 10. ^{{Cite journal|last=Berlant|first=Jeffrey|title=Profession and Monopoly: a study of medicine in the United States and Great Britain|journal=Medical History|volume=20|issue=3|pages=342|year=1975|isbn=978-0-520-02734-3|pmc=1081816}} 11. ^{{cite book|last=Percival|first=Thomas|title=Medical ethics|publisher=John Henry Parker|pages=49–57 esp section 8 p. 52|url=https://books.google.com/?id=yVUEAAAAQAAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=medical+ethics|year=1849}} 12. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.uab.edu/reynolds/MajMedFigs/Percival.htm |title=Archived copy |accessdate=2007-10-16 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20060704201058/http://www.uab.edu/reynolds/MajMedFigs/Percival.htm |archivedate=2006-07-04 |df= }} 13. ^Walter, Klein eds. The Story of Bioethics: From seminal works to contemporary explorations. 14. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Lakhan SE, Hamlat E, McNamee T, Laird C |title=Time for a unified approach to medical ethics |journal=Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine |volume=4 |issue=3 |year=2009 |pmid=19737406 |doi=10.1186/1747-5341-4-13 |page=13 |pmc=2745426}} 15. ^{{cite journal|last=Gillon|first=R|title=Medical ethics: four principles plus attention to scope|journal=British Medical Journal|year=1994|volume=309|issue=184|pages=184–188|doi=10.1136/bmj.309.6948.184|pmid=8044100|pmc=2540719}} 16. ^{{Cite journal|last1=Murgic|first1=L.|last2=Hébert|first2=P.C.|last3=Sovic|first3=S.|last4=Pavlekovic|first4=G.|title=Paternalism and autonomy: views of patients and providers in a transitional (post-communist) country|journal=BMC Medical Ethics|volume=16|issue=65}} 17. ^{{Cite journal | last1 = Pollard | first1 = B. J. | title = Autonomy and paternalism in medicine | journal = The Medical Journal of Australia | volume = 159 | issue = 11–12 | pages = 797–802 | year = 1993 | pmid = 8264472}} 18. ^{{Cite journal|last=Burla|first=Claudia|date=2014|title=Alzheimer, Dementia and the living will: a proposal|pmc=4078222|journal=Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy|volume=17|issue=3|pages=389–395|doi=10.1007/s11019-014-9559-8|pmid=24737537}} 19. ^{{cite web |url=https://www.bma.org.uk/advice/employment/ethics/mental-capacity/assessing-mental-capacity |title=Assessing mental capacity |publisher=BMA |date= |accessdate=2018-05-24 |deadurl=no |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20180525062740/https://www.bma.org.uk/advice/employment/ethics/mental-capacity/assessing-mental-capacity |archivedate=2018-05-25 |df= }} 20. ^{{cite journal | author = Ryan CJ | year = 2010 | title = Ethical issues, part 2: ethics, psychiatry, and end-of-life issues | url = http://www.searchmedica.com/resource.html?rurl=http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/cognitive-impairment/content/article/10168/1583693&q=christopher+j+ryan&c=ps&ss=psychTimesLink&p=Convera&fr=true&ds=0&srid=1 | journal = Psychiatr Times | volume = 27 | issue = 6 | pages = 26–27 }}{{dead link|date=January 2018 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }} 21. ^{{Cite journal|last=Jotterand|first=Fabrice|date=2005-01-01|title=The Hippocratic Oath and Contemporary Medicine: Dialectic Between Past Ideals and Present Reality?|url=https://academic.oup.com/jmp/article-abstract/30/1/107/893486|journal=The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy|language=en|volume=30|issue=1|pages=107–128|doi=10.1080/03605310590907084|pmid=15814370|issn=0360-5310|deadurl=no|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20180408015006/https://academic.oup.com/jmp/article-abstract/30/1/107/893486|archivedate=2018-04-08|df=}} 22. ^Medical.Webends.com > Double effect {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100905010101/http://medical.webends.com/kw/Double%2BEffect |date=2010-09-05 }} Retrieved September 2010 23. ^Page 424 in:{{cite book|title=Primary hematology|author=Tefferi, Ayalew|publisher=Humana Press|year=2001|isbn=978-0-89603-664-2|location=Totowa, NJ|pages=|doi=|oclc=|accessdate=}} [https://books.google.com/books?id=vYqJoUFFM2wC&pg=PA424&lpg] 24. ^{{vcite book | author = Randall F | chapter = Ethical issues in cancer pain management | editor = Sykes N, Bennett MI & Yuan C-S | title = Clinical pain management: Cancer pain | edition = 2nd | isbn = 978-0-340-94007-5 | publisher = Hodder Arnold | location = London | pages = 93–100 | year = 2008 }} 25. ^{{vcite web | author=World Medical Association | home=http://www.wma.net | title=Principal features of medical ethics | url=http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/30ethicsmanual/pdf/chap_1_en.pdf | date= | accessdate=3 November 2015 | deadurl=yes | archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304190742/http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/30ethicsmanual/pdf/chap_1_en.pdf | archivedate=4 March 2016 | df= }} 26. ^Article 20(1). European Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131109110632/http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/EN/Treaties/html/164.htm |date=2013-11-09 }} (1997). Adopted at Oviedo, 4 April 1997. 27. ^Table of Ratifications and Accessions {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131203061719/http://www.conventions.coe.int/Treaty/Commun/ChercheSig.asp?NT=164&CM=8&DF=30%2F11%2F2013&CL=ENG |date=2013-12-03 }}. 28. ^UNESCO. Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171010174232/http://portal.unesco.org/en/ev.php-URL_ID%3D31058%26URL_DO%3DDO_TOPIC%26URL_SECTION%3D201.html |date=2017-10-10 }}. Adopted by the UNESCO General Conference at Paris, 19 October 2005. 29. ^{{cite web|url=http://site.ebrary.com/lib/michstate/reader.action?docID=10021934|title=Euthanasia, Ethics and Public Policy: an Argument against Legislation|last=Keown|first=John|date=2002|website=Protest ebrary|access-date=}}{{dead link|date=August 2017|bot=medic}}{{cbignore|bot=medic}} 30. ^{{cite web|url=Health_Insurance_Portability_and_Accountability_Act|title=|last=|first=|date=|website=|archive-url=|archive-date=|dead-url=|access-date=}} 31. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.ncsl.org/IssuesResearch/Health/AbortionLaws/tabid/14401/Default.aspx#parent|title=Legislative News, Studies and Analysis - National Conference of State Legislatures|first=National Conference of State|last=Legislatures|website=www.ncsl.org|deadurl=no|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20100224232857/http://www.ncsl.org/IssuesResearch/Health/AbortionLaws/tabid/14401/Default.aspx#parent|archivedate=2010-02-24|df=}} 32. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.ncsl.org/programs/health/aborlaws.htm |title=National Conference of State Legislatures > Abortion Laws > Parental Involvement in Minors' Abortions |publisher=Webarchive.loc.gov |date= |accessdate=2018-05-24 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=http://webarchive.loc.gov/all/20090429230410/http://www.ncsl.org/programs/health/aborlaws.htm |archivedate=2009-04-29 |df= }} 33. ^Appel, JM. Must My Doctor Tell My Partner? Rethinking Confidentiality In the HIV Era, Medicine and Health Rhode Island, Jun 2006 34. ^{{cite journal|vauthors=Eysenbach G, Till JE|year=2001|title=Ethical issues in qualitative research on internet communities|journal=BMJ|volume=323|issue=7321|pages=1103–05|doi=10.1136/bmj.323.7321.1103|pmc=59687|pmid=11701577}} 35. ^1 {{cite journal|author=Bruckman A|year=2002|title=Studying the amateur artist: A perspective on disguising data collected in human subjects research on the Internet|journal=Ethics and Information Technology|volume=4|issue=3|pages=217–31|doi=10.1023/A:1021316409277}} 36. ^{{cite journal|author=Turkle S|year=1994|title=Constructions and Reconstructions of Self in Virtual Reality|journal=Mind, Culture, and Activity|volume=1|issue=3|pages=158–67|doi=10.1080/10749039409524667}} 37. ^{{cite journal|author=Turkle S|year=1997|title=Multiple subjectivity and virtual community at the end of the Freudian century|journal=Sociological Inquiry|volume=67|issue=1|pages=72–84|doi=10.1111/j.1475-682X.1997.tb00430.x}} 38. ^Rains S. A. Bosch L. A. Privacy and Health in the Information Age: A Content Analysis of Health Web Site Privacy Policy Statements. Health Communication. 2009 Vol. 24 s.l. 39. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.prnewsnow.com/Public_Release/Managed_Care_And_HMO/209319.html|title=Archived copy|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20081202045045/http://www.prnewsnow.com/Public_Release/Managed_Care_And_HMO/209319.html|archivedate=2008-12-02|deadurl=yes|accessdate=2008-09-14|df=}}{{cite journal|author=PRNewsNow.com|last2=Priest|first2=ER|year=2007|title=Physicians Competing for TopTen Search Engine Placements Find Success Inexpensive|journal=JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association|volume=267|issue=13|pages=1810–12|doi=10.1001/jama.267.13.1810|pmid=1545466}} 40. ^{{Cite journal|last=Goodyear|first=Micheal D.E|date=2007|title=The Declaration of Helsinki|url=http://search.proquest.com/docview/1777992607|journal=British Medical Journal|volume=|pages=}} 41. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.gmc-uk.org/guidance/good_medical_practice/index.asp |title=Good medical practice - GMC |publisher=Gmc-uk.org |date= |accessdate=2018-05-24 |deadurl=no |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20081221112745/http://www.gmc-uk.org/guidance/good_medical_practice/index.asp |archivedate=2008-12-21 |df= }} 42. ^ {{dead link|date=September 2017|bot=InternetArchiveBot|fix-attempted=yes}} 43. ^{{Cite journal|last=Wisnewski|first=Jeremy|date=December 2015|title=Perceiving Sympathetically: Moral Perception, Embodiment, and Medical Ethics|doi=10.1007/s10912-015-9349-1|pmid=26164290|journal=Journal of Medical Humanities|volume=36|issue=4|pages=309–319}} 44. ^{{Cite journal|last=Asgary, Junck|first=Ramin, Emily|year=2013|title=New trends of short-term humanitarian medical volunteerism: professional and ethical considerations|url=|journal=Journal of Medical Ethics|volume=39|issue=10|pages=625–631|via=ProQuest|doi=10.1136/medethics-2011-100488|pmid=23236086}} 45. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Bekelman JE, Li Y, Gross CP |title=Scope and impact of financial conflicts of interest in biomedical research: a systematic review |journal=JAMA |volume=289 |issue=4 |pages=454–65 |year=2003 |pmid=12533125 |doi=10.1001/jama.289.4.454}} 46. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Ross JS, Lackner JE, Lurie P, Gross CP, Wolfe S, Krumholz HM |title=Pharmaceutical company payments to physicians: early experiences with disclosure laws in Vermont and Minnesota |journal=JAMA |volume=297 |issue=11 |pages=1216–23 |year=2007 |pmid=17374816 |doi=10.1001/jama.297.11.1216}} 47. ^{{cite journal |doi=10.1056/NEJM199211193272107 |vauthors=Swedlow A, Johnson G, Smithline N, Milstein A |title=Increased costs and rates of use in the California workers' compensation system as a result of self-referral by physicians |journal=N Engl J Med |volume=327 |issue=21 |pages=1502–6 |year=1992 |pmid=1406882}} 48. ^{{cite journal |author=Jordan, M. C. |title=Ethics manual. Fourth edition. American College of Physicians |journal=Ann Intern Med |volume=128 |issue=7 |pages=576–94 |year=1998 |pmid=9518406 |url=http://www.annals.org/cgi/content/full/128/7/576 |doi=10.1001/archinte.128.4.576 |deadurl=no |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20070202090708/http://www.annals.org/cgi/content/full/128/7/576 |archivedate=2007-02-02 |df= }} 49. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Güldal D, Semin S |title=The influences of drug companies' advertising programs on physicians |journal=Int J Health Serv |volume=30 |issue=3 |pages=585–95 |year=2000 |pmid=11109183 |doi=10.2190/GYW9-XUMQ-M3K2-T31C}} 50. ^{{cite journal |author=Wazana A |title=Physicians and the pharmaceutical industry: is a gift ever just a gift? |journal=JAMA |volume=283 |issue=3 |pages=373–80 |year=2000 |pmid=10647801 |doi=10.1001/jama.283.3.373|pmc=1488237 }} 51. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Blake R, Early E |title=Patients' attitudes about gifts to physicians from pharmaceutical companies |journal=J Am Board Fam Pract |volume=8 |issue=6 |pages=457–64 |year=1995 |pmid=8585404}} 52. ^LA Times, "Drug money withdrawals: Medical schools review rules on pharmaceutical freebies" {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070312091308/http://www.montereyherald.com/mld/montereyherald/living/health/16680875.htm |date=2007-03-12 }}, posted 2/12/07, accessed 3/6/07 53. ^JH Medicine Policy on Interaction with Industry {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111205021038/http://www.hopkinsmedicine.org/Research/OPC/Policy_Industry_Interaction/policy_interaction_industry.html |date=2011-12-05 }} effective date July 1, 2009, accessed July 20, 2011 54. ^American Medical Association Journal of Ethics May 2012, Volume 14, Number 5: 396-397 55. ^1 {{cite journal | author = Chen FM, Feudtner C, Rhodes LA, Green LA | year = 2001 | title = Role conflicts of physicians and their family members: rules but no rulebook | url = | journal = Western Journal of Medicine | volume = 175 | issue = 4| pages = 236–239 | pmid=11577049| pmc = 1071568| doi = 10.1136/ewjm.175.4.236 }} 56. ^{{cite journal |doi=10.1056/NEJM199110313251806 |vauthors=La Puma J, Stocking C, La Voie D, Darling C |title=When physicians treat members of their own families. Practices in a community hospital |journal=N Engl J Med |volume=325 |issue=18 |pages=1290–4 |year=1991 |pmid=1922224}} 57. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=La Puma J, Priest E |title=Is there a doctor in the house? An analysis of the practice of physicians' treating their own families |journal=JAMA |volume=267 |issue=13 |pages=1810–2 |year=1992 |pmid=1545466 |doi=10.1001/jama.267.13.1810}} 58. ^{{Cite journal|last=Collier|first=Roger|date=March 2016|title=When the doctor-patient relationship turns sexual|url=http://go.galegroup.com/ps/i.do?p=AONE&u=msu_main&id=GALE|A444400220&v=2.1&it=r&sid=summon&authCount=1|journal=Canadian Medical Association Journal|volume=188|issue=4|pages=247–248|doi=10.1503/cmaj.109-5230|pmid=26858353|pmc=4771530}} 59. ^{{Cite journal|last=AbuDagga, Wolfe, Carome, Oshel|first=Azza, Sidney, Michael, Robert|date=February 2016|title=Cross-Sectional Analysis of the 1039 U.S. Physicians Reported to the National Practitioner Data Bank for Sexual Misconduct, 2003–2013|journal=PLOS One|volume=11|issue=2|pages=e0147800|doi=10.1371/journal.pone.0147800|pmid=26840639|pmc=4739584}} 60. ^{{cite journal |vauthors=Gartrell N, Milliken N, Goodson W, Thiemann S, Lo B |title=Physician-patient sexual contact. Prevalence and problems |journal=West J Med |volume=157 |issue=2 |pages=139–43 |year=1992 |pmid=1441462 |pmc=1011231}} 61. ^JM Appel. May Physicians Date Their Patients’ Relatives? Rethinking Sexual Misconduct & Disclosure After Long v. Ostroff, Medicine & Health, Rhode Island, May 2004
External links
1 : Medical ethics |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。