词条 | Proof by contradiction |
释义 |
In logic, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or validity of a proposition by first assuming that the opposite proposition is true, and then shows that such an assumption leads to a contradiction. Proof by contradiction is also known as indirect proof, proof by assuming the opposite, and reductio ad impossibile. It is a particular kind of the more general form of argument known as reductio ad absurdum.[1][2] G. H. Hardy described proof by contradiction as "one of a mathematician's finest weapons", saying "It is a far finer gambit than any chess gambit: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game."[1]PrincipleProof by contradiction is based on the law of noncontradiction as first formalized as a metaphysical principle by Aristotle. Noncontradiction is also a theorem in propositional logic. This states that an assertion or mathematical statement cannot be both true and false. That is, a proposition Q and its negation Q ("not-Q") cannot both be true. In a proof by contradiction, it is shown that the denial of the statement being proved results in such a contradiction. It has the form of a reductio ad absurdum argument. If P is the proposition to be proved:
An alternate form derives a contradiction with the statement to be proved itself:
An existence proof by contradiction assumes that some object doesn't exist, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object must exist. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical proofs, not every school of mathematical thought accepts this kind of nonconstructive proof as universally valid. Law of the excluded middle{{main|Law of the excluded middle}}Proof by contradiction also depends on the law of the excluded middle, also first formulated by Aristotle. This states that either an assertion or its negation must be true (For all propositions P, either P or not-P is true) That is, there is no other truth value besides "true" and "false" that a proposition can take. Combined with the principle of noncontradiction, this means that exactly one of and is true. In proof by contradiction, this permits the conclusion that since the possibility of has been excluded, must be true. The law of the excluded middle is accepted in virtually all formal logics; however, some intuitionist mathematicians do not accept it, and thus reject proof by contradiction as a proof technique. {{anchor|rel}}Relationship with other proof techniques{{unreferenced section|date=January 2017}}Proof by contradiction is closely related to proof by contrapositive, and the two are sometimes confused, though they are distinct methods. The main distinction is that a proof by contrapositive applies only to statements that can be written in the form (i.e., implications), whereas the technique of proof by contradiction applies to statements of any form:
This corresponds, in the framework of propositional logic, to the equivalence , where is the logical contradiction, or false value. In the case where the statement to be proven is an implication , let us look at the differences between direct proof, proof by contrapositive, and proof by contradiction:
This corresponds to the equivalence .
This corresponds to the equivalences . ExamplesIrrationality of the square root of 2A classic proof by contradiction from mathematics is the proof that the square root of 2 is irrational.[3] If it were rational, it could be expressed as a fraction a/b in lowest terms, where a and b are integers, at least one of which is odd. But if a/b = {{radic|2}}, then a2 = 2b2. Therefore, a2 must be even. Because the square of an odd number is odd, that in turn implies that a is even. This means that b must be odd because a/b is in lowest terms. On the other hand, if a is even, then a2 is a multiple of 4. If a2 is a multiple of 4 and a2 = 2b2, then 2b2 is a multiple of 4, and therefore b2 is even, and so is b. So b is odd and even, a contradiction. Therefore, the initial assumption—that {{radic|2}} can be expressed as a fraction—must be false. The length of the hypotenuseThe method of proof by contradiction has also been used to show that for any non-degenerate right triangle, the length of the hypotenuse is less than the sum of the lengths of the two remaining sides.[4] The proof relies on the Pythagorean theorem. Letting c be the length of the hypotenuse and a and b the lengths of the legs, the claim is that a + b > c. The claim is negated to assume that a + b ≤ c. Squaring both sides results in (a + b)2 ≤ c2 or, equivalently, a2 + 2ab + b2 ≤ c2. A triangle is non-degenerate if each edge has positive length, so it may be assumed that a and b are greater than 0. Therefore, a2 + b2 < a2 + 2ab + b2 ≤ c2. The transitive relation may be reduced to a2 + b2 < c2. It is known from the Pythagorean theorem that a2 + b2 = c2. This results in a contradiction since strict inequality and equality are mutually exclusive. The latter was a result of the Pythagorean theorem and the former the assumption that a + b ≤ c. The contradiction means that it is impossible for both to be true and it is known that the Pythagorean theorem holds. It follows that the assumption that a + b ≤ c must be false and hence a + b > c, proving the claim. No least positive rational numberConsider the proposition, P: "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0". In a proof by contradiction, we start by assuming the opposite, ¬P: that there is a smallest rational number, say, r. Now r/2 is a rational number greater than 0 and smaller than r. But that contradicts our initial assumption, ¬P, that r was the smallest rational number. (In the above symbolic argument, "r is the smallest rational number" would be Q and "r/2 is a rational number smaller than r" would be ¬Q.) So we can conclude that the original proposition, P, must be true — "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0". OtherFor other examples, see proof that the square root of 2 is not rational (where indirect proofs different from the above one can be found) and Cantor's diagonal argument. NotationProofs by contradiction sometimes end with the word "Contradiction!". Isaac Barrow and Baermann used the notation Q.E.A., for "quod est absurdum" ("which is absurd"), along the lines of Q.E.D., but this notation is rarely used today.[5]{{citation needed|reason=1. A board is no reliable source. 2. It's more likely that it was "Q. E. D." and "Q. E. A." (with spaces) in those older times, not "Q.E.D." (without spaces). Also: It should be the case, that also other people (like Leibniz) used "Q. E. A." or at least "quod est absurdum".|date=December 2015}} A graphical symbol sometimes used for contradictions is a downwards zigzag arrow "lightning" symbol (U+21AF: ↯), for example in Davey and Priestley.[6] Others sometimes used include a pair of opposing arrows (as or ), struck-out arrows (), a stylized form of hash (such as U+2A33: ⨳), or the "reference mark" (U+203B: ※).[7][8] The "up tack" symbol (U+22A5: ⊥) used by philosophers and logicians (see contradiction) also appears, but is often avoided due to its usage for orthogonality. Principle of explosion{{main|Principle of explosion}}A curious logical consequence of the principle of non-contradiction is that a contradiction implies any statement; if a contradiction is accepted as true, any proposition (or its negation) can be proved from it.[9] This is known as the principle of explosion ({{lang-la|ex falso quodlibet|links=no}}, "from a falsehood, anything [follows]", or {{lang|la|ex contradictione sequitur quodlibet}}, "from a contradiction, anything follows"), or the principle of pseudo-scotus. (for all Q, P and not-P implies Q) Thus a contradiction in a formal axiomatic system is disastrous; since any theorem can be proven true it destroys the conventional meaning of truth and falsity. The discovery of contradictions at the foundations of mathematics at the beginning of the 20th century, such as Russell's paradox, threatened the entire structure of mathematics due to the principle of explosion. This motivated a great deal of work during the 20th century to create consistent axiomatic systems to provide a logical underpinning for mathematics. This has also led a few philosophers such as Newton da Costa, Walter Carnielli and Graham Priest to reject the principle of non-contradiction, giving rise to theories such as paraconsistent logic and dialethism, which accepts that there exist statements that are both true and false. See also
References1. ^1 G. H. Hardy, A Mathematician's Apology; Cambridge University Press, 1992. {{ISBN|9780521427067}}. [https://www.math.ualberta.ca/mss/misc/A%20Mathematician's%20Apology.pdf PDF p.19]. 2. ^S. M. Cohen, "Introduction to Logic", [https://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/120/Chapter5.pdf Chapter 5] "proof by contradiction ... Also called indirect proof or reductio ad absurdum ..." 3. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.math.utah.edu/~pa/math/q1.html|title=Why is the square root of 2 irrational?|last=Alfeld|first=Peter|date=16 August 1996|work=Understanding Mathematics, a study guide|publisher=Department of Mathematics, University of Utah|accessdate=6 February 2013}} 4. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.cs.utexas.edu/~pstone/Courses/313Hfall12/resources/week2a-pp4.pdf|title=Logic, Sets, and Functions: Honors|last=Stone|first=Peter|work=Course materials|publisher=Department of Computer Sciences, The University of Texas at Austin|accessdate=6 February 2013|location=pp 14–23}} 5. ^{{cite web|url=http://mathforum.org/kb/message.jspa?messageID=1175481|title=Math Forum Discussions|publisher=}} 6. ^B. Davey and H.A. Priestley, Introduction to lattices and order, Cambridge University Press, 2002. 7. ^The Comprehensive LaTeX Symbol List, pg. 20. http://www.ctan.org/tex-archive/info/symbols/comprehensive/symbols-a4.pdf 8. ^Gary Hardegree, Introduction to Modal Logic, Chapter 2, pg. II–2. https://web.archive.org/web/20110607061046/http://people.umass.edu/gmhwww/511/pdf/c02.pdf 9. ^{{cite book | last1 = Ferguson | first1 = Thomas Macaulay | last2 = Priest | first2 = Graham | title = A Dictionary of Logic | publisher = Oxford University Press | date = 2016 | location = | pages = 146 | language = | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=2Q5nDAAAQBAJ&pg=PT146&dq=%22principle+of+non-contradiction%22 | doi = | id = | isbn = 0192511556 }} Further reading and external links{{wikibooks|1=Mathematical Proof|2=Methods of Proof/Proof by Contradiction|3=Proof by Contradiction}}
3 : Mathematical proofs|Methods of proof|Theorems in propositional logic |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。