请输入您要查询的百科知识:

 

词条 Dubins–Spanier theorems
释义

  1. Setting

  2. Statements

  3. Corollaries

      Consensus partition    Super-proportional division  

  4. Sketch of Proof

      Utilitarian-optimal division    Leximin-optimal division  

  5. Further developments

  6. See also

  7. References

The Dubins–Spanier theorems are several theorems in the theory of fair cake-cutting. They were published by Lester Dubins and Edwin Spanier in 1961.[1] Although the original motivation for these theorems is fair division, they are in fact general theorems in measure theory.

Setting

There is a set , and a set which is a sigma-algebra of subsets of .

There are partners. Every partner has a personal value measure . This function determines how much each subset of is worth to that partner.

Let a partition of to measurable sets: . Define the matrix as the following matrix:

This matrix contains the valuations of all players to all pieces of the partition.

Let be the collection of all such matrices (for the same value measures, the same , and different partitions):

The Dubins–Spanier theorems deal with the topological properties of .

Statements

If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic, then:

  • is a compact set;
  • is a convex set.

This was already proved by Dvoretzky, Wald, and Wolfowitz. [2]

Corollaries

Consensus partition

A cake partition to k pieces is called a consensus partition with weights (also called exact division) if:

I.e, there is a consensus among all partners that the value of piece j is exactly .

Suppose, from now on, that are weights whose sum is 1:

and the value measures are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1:

The convexity part of the DS theorem implies that:[1]{{rp|5}}

If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

then a consensus partition exists.

PROOF: For every , define a partition as follows:

In the partition , all partners value the -th piece as 1 and all other pieces as 0. Hence, in the matrix , there are ones on the -th column and zeros everywhere else.

By convexity, there is a partition such that:

In that matrix, the -th column contains only the value . This means that, in the partition , all partners value the -th piece as exactly .

Note: this corollary confirms a previous assertion by Hugo Steinhaus. It also gives an affirmative answer to the problem of the Nile provided that there are only a finite number of flood heights.

Super-proportional division

A cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called a super-proportional division with weights if:

I.e, the piece allotted to partner is strictly more valuable for him than what he deserves. The following statement is Dubins-Spanier Theorem on the existence of super-proportional division {{rp|6}}

{{math_theorem
|With these notations, let be weights whose sum is 1, assume that the point is an interior point of the (n-1)-dimensional simplex with coordinates pairwise different, and assume that the value measures are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1 (i.e. they are non-atomic probability measures). If at least two of the measures are not equal ( ), then super-proportional divisions exist.}}

The hypothesis that the value measures are not identical is necessary. Otherwise, the sum leads to a contradiction.

Namely, if all value measures are countably-additive and non-atomic, and if there are two partners such that ,

then a super-proportional division exists.I.e, the necessary condition is also sufficient.

Sketch of Proof

Suppose w.l.o.g. that . Then there is some piece of the cake, , such that . Let be the complement of ; then . This means that . However, . Hence, either or . Suppose w.l.o.g. that and are true.

Define the following partitions:

  • : the partition that gives to partner 1, to partner 2, and nothing to all others.
  • (for ): the partition that gives the entire cake to partner and nothing to all others.

Here, we are interested only in the diagonals of the matrices , which represent the valuations of the partners to their own pieces:

  • In , entry 1 is , entry 2 is , and the other entries are 0.
  • In (for ), entry is 1 and the other entires are 0.

By convexity, for every set of weights there is a partition such that:

It is possible to select the weights such that, in the diagonal of , the entries are in the same ratios as the weights . Since we assumed that , it is possible to prove that , so is a super-proportional division.

Utilitarian-optimal division

A cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called utilitarian-optimal if it maximizes the sum of values. I.e, it maximizes:

Utilitarian-optimal divisions do not always exist. For example, suppose is the set of positive integers. There are two partners. Both value the entire set as 1. Partner 1 assigns a positive value to every integer and partner 2 assigns zero value to every finite subset. From a utilitarian point of view, it is best to give partner 1 a large finite subset and give the remainder to partner 2. When the set given to partner 1 becomes larger and larger, the sum-of-values becomes closer and closer to 2, but it never approaches 2. So there is no utilitarian-optimal division.

The problem with the above example is that the value measure of partner 2 is finitely-additive but not countably-additive.

The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:[1]{{rp|7}}

If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

then a utilitarian-optimal division exists.

In this special case, non-atomicity is not required: if all value measures are countably-additive, then a utilitarian-optimal partition exists.[1]{{rp|7}}

Leximin-optimal division

A cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called leximin-optimal with weights if it maximizes the lexicographically-ordered vector of relative values. I.e, it maximizes the following vector:

where the partners are indexed such that:

A leximin-optimal partition maximizes the value of the poorest partner (relative to his weight); subject to that, it maximizes the value of the next-poorest partner (relative to his weight); etc.

The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:[1]{{rp|8}}

If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

then a leximin-optimal division exists.

Further developments

  • The leximin-optimality criterion, introduced by Dubins and Spanier, has been studied extensively later. In particular, in the problem of cake-cutting, it was studied by Marco Dall'Aglio.[3]

See also

  • Lyapunov vector-measure theorem[4]
  • Weller's theorem

References

1. ^{{Cite journal | doi = 10.2307/2311357| jstor = 2311357| title = How to Cut a Cake Fairly| journal = The American Mathematical Monthly| volume = 68| pages = 1| year = 1961| last1 = Dubins | first1 = Lester Eli| last2 = Spanier | first2 = Edwin Henry}}
2. ^{{Cite journal|doi=10.2140/pjm.1951.1.59|title=Relations among certain ranges of vector measures|journal=Pacific Journal of Mathematics|volume=1|pages=59|year=1951|last1=Dvoretzky|first1=A.|last2=Wald|first2=A.|last3=Wolfowitz|first3=J.}}
3. ^{{Cite journal|doi=10.1016/S0377-0427(99)00393-3|title=The Dubins–Spanier optimization problem in fair division theory|journal=Journal of Computational and Applied Mathematics|volume=130|pages=17|year=2001|last1=Dall'Aglio|first1=Marco}}
4. ^{{cite journal|last1=Neyman|first1=J|title=Un théorèm dʼexistence|journal=C. R. Acad. Sci.|date=1946|volume=222|pages=843–845}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Dubins-Spanier theorems}}

2 : Fair division|Measure theory

随便看

 

开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。

 

Copyright © 2023 OENC.NET All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/11/10 15:51:33