词条 | Hard determinism |
释义 |
Hard determinism (or metaphysical determinism) is a view on free will which holds that determinism is true, and that it is incompatible with free will, and, therefore, that free will does not exist. Although hard determinism generally refers to nomological determinism,[1] it can also be a position taken with respect to other forms of determinism that necessitate the future in its entirety.[2] Hard determinism is contrasted with soft determinism, which is a compatibilist form of determinism, holding that free will may exist despite determinism.[3] It is also contrasted with metaphysical libertarianism, the other major form of incompatibilism which holds that free will exists and determinism is false. In historyIn ancient Greece, Socrates initiated the rationalistic teaching that any agent is obliged to pursue the chief good conceived by his or her mind.[4] The peripatetic naturalist Strato of Lampsacus speculated that an unconscious divine power acts in the world and causes the origin, growth, and breakdown of things.[5] Diodorus Cronus asserted the identity of the possible and the necessary and inferred that future events are as determined as the past ones.[6] Chrysippus refuted the "idle argument" invented to discredit determinism as if human efforts were futile in a preordained world; he explained that fated events occur with the engagement of conscious agents.[7] In the 17th century, both Locke[8] and Spinoza[9] argued for strict causality of volitional acts. In the age of enlightenment, Baron d’Holbach[10] promulgated the naturalistic interpretation of mental events. Schopenhauer observed that everyone regards himself free a priori; however, a posteriori he must discover that he had been obliged to make the decisions he actually made.[11] Nietzsche noticed that free decisions are graded as causa sui, emerging from non-existence.[12] Recently Daniel Wegner stressed the limitations of free will on grounds of experimental evidence for unconscious choice and action.[13] To prove determinism, the following putative experiment was proposed: all principal differences between the features of an artificial zygote and that developing naturally can be avoided.[14] OverviewMeeting a challenge, agents make decisions in conformity to the inherited character, life history, and current stimuli. The field of acute attention is limited, and motives partly remain unconscious. From the first person's perspective, we have an intuitive commitment that many options are available. However, if the total of the mental content is considered from the third person's perspective, only a single decision deemed by the agent as the most favorable at the moment turns out real. The validity of causation for any mental event becomes apparent taking into account their neurophysiological correlates.[15] Different causal descriptions correspond to the mental and physical domain.[16] Laws of thermodynamics and quantum mechanics govern the latter. Admitting downright mental causation of physiological impulses would mean surplus determination. The surmise that under identical conditions, alternative decisions and actions are possible is disproved by naturalists as an illusion.[17] Hard determinism is not taken to refer merely to a determinism on earth, but in all of reality (e.g. involving the effects of light from other galaxies, etc.); not just during a certain deterministic period of time, but for all time. This also means that the relation of necessity will be bi-directional. Just as the initial conditions of the universe presumably determine all future states, so too does the present necessitate the past. In other words, one could not change any one fact without affecting the entire timeline. Because hard determinists often support this eternalist view of time, they do not believe that there are genuine chances or possibilities, only the idea that events are 100% likely.[18] Unlike "law fundamentalists", some philosophers are "law pluralists": they question what it means to have a law of physics. One example is the "Best Standards Analysis", which says that the laws are only useful ways to summarize all past events, rather than there being metaphysically "pushy" entities (this route still brings one into conflict with the idea of free will).{{citation needed|date=February 2012}} Some law pluralists further believe there are simply no laws of physics.[18] The mathematical universe hypothesis suggests that there are other universes in which the laws of physics and fundamental constants are different. Andreas Albrecht of Imperial College in London called it a "provocative" solution to one of the central problems facing physics. Although he "wouldn't dare" go so far as to say he believes it, he noted that "it's actually quite difficult to construct a theory where everything we see is all there is".[19] The feasibility of testing determinism is always challenged by what we know, or think we can know, about the idea of a final, all-encompassing, theory of everything. Some physicists challenge the likelihood of determinism on the grounds that certain interpretations of quantum mechanics stipulate that the universe is fundamentally indeterministic, such as the Copenhagen interpretation; whereas other interpretations are deterministic, for example, the De Broglie-Bohm Theory and the many-worlds interpretation. Chaos theory describes how a deterministic system can exhibit perplexing behavior that is difficult to predict: as in the butterfly effect, minor variations between the starting conditions of two systems can result in major differences. Yet chaos theory is a wholly deterministic thesis; it merely demonstrates the potential for vastly different consequences from very similar initial conditions. Properly understood, then, it enlightens and reinforces the deterministic claim.[18]Implications for ethics{{see also|Moral responsibility}}Hard determinists reject free will. Critics often suggest that, in so doing, the hard determinist also rejects ethics. The key to this argument rests on the idea that holding a person morally responsible requires them to make a choice between two, or more, truly possible alternatives. If choice is indeed impossible, then it would be incorrect to hold anyone morally responsible for his or her actions. If this argument holds, hard determinists are restricted to moral nihilism. This feature, however, is tenable only as far as hard determinists discard responsibility. In a necessitarian world, recourse to merit and blameworthiness is toned down while adherence to ethical and legal values is not ruined. Persons may be appreciated as carriers, executors, and defenders of morality. Alternatively, the choice to be regretful of past misdeeds becomes unreasonable. Nevertheless, one can admonish oneself for one's lapses and resolve to avoid similar behavior in the future.[20] Those hard determinists who defend ethical realism would object to the premise that contra-causal free will is necessary for ethics. Those who are also ethically naturalistic may also point out that there are good reasons to punish criminals: it is a chance to modify their behaviour, or their punishment can act as a deterrent for others who would otherwise act in the same manner. The hard determinist could even argue that this understanding of the true and various causes of a psychopath's behaviour, for instance, allow them to respond even more reasonably or compassionately.[21] Hard determinists acknowledge that humans do, in some sense, "choose", or deliberate – although in a way that obeys natural laws. For example, a hard determinist might see humans as a sort of thinking machines, but believe it is inaccurate to say they "came to a decision" or "chose". Generalization of event causation should circumvent overstatement of external impulses. Autotelic personalities show a high rate of activities all by themselves. The capacity to resist psychological assault is impressive evidence of autarkic resources. Determinists even admit that with corresponding knowledge, changes in the genetic depository and consequently behavior are possible. Up to now, the concepts and terminology of legal affairs follow the pre-reflexive belief in alternative possibilities. As scientific insight advances, the juridical attitude becomes increasingly "external": there should be fewer emotions about offender's will and more concern about the effects of offenses on society. The retributive function of punishment should be rejected as irrational and unjustified. "Lex talionis" is discarded already because of deficient correlation between crime and penalty. If the inveterate notion of "mens rea" is used at all, then only to distinguish intentional actions from inadvertent ones and not to designate an autonomous undertaking of the lawbreaker. At the same time, it is justified to require the perpetrator to critically reconsider his intentions and character, to demand apology and compensation in victims' favor. The rehabilitation service should be used to train the risky circle for keeping the norms of social life.[22] Psychological effects of belief in hard determinismSome behavioral anomalies have been observed in persons cultivating the habit of causal awareness. Increased aggressiveness, excessive compliance, and reduced helpfulness are reported. Critical assessment of one's own former conduct appeared abated.[23] William James was an American pragmatist philosopher who coined the terms "soft determinist" and "hard determinist" in an influential essay titled "The Dilemma of Determinism".[24] He argued against determinism, holding that the important issue is not personal responsibility, but hope. He believed that thorough-going determinism leads either to a bleak pessimism or to a degenerate subjectivism in moral judgment. He proposed the way to escape the dilemma is to allow a role for chance. James was careful to explain that he would rather "debate about objects than words,” which indicates he did not insist on saying that replacing determinism with a model including chance had to mean we had "free will.” The determinist would counter-argue that there is still reason for hope. Whether or not the universe is determined does not change the fact that the future is unknown, and might very well always be. From a naturalist point of view, a person's actions still play a role in the shape of that future. Founder and director of the Center of Naturalism, Thomas W. Clark, explains that humans are not merely the playthings of patterned, natural forces in the universe –but rather we are ourselves examples of those forces.[25] The deterministic view aligns our representations with the faculties and possibilities we actually possess but it should avoid misleading introspection. Admitting agents’ dependence on a drastic background can enhance insight, moderate severity and spare unproductive suffering.[26] In so far as the mind comprehends universal necessity, the power of emotions is diminished.[27] See also
References1. ^{{cite encyclopedia|last=Vihvelin |first=Kadri |editor=Edward N. Zalta | title=Arguments for Incompatibilism | encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy| edition=Spring 2011 | year=2011 | url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/incompatibilism-arguments}} {{Use dmy dates|date=March 2011}}{{Determinism}}2. ^{{cite book|author=Raymond J. VanArragon|title=Key Terms in Philosophy of Religion|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JyTohO1AMzwC|accessdate=22 December 2012|date=21 October 2010|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|isbn=978-1-4411-3867-5|page=21}} 3. ^Philosophy-Dictionary.org on "Hard Determinism" 4. ^Plato, Protagoras, 345e; 358c. 5. ^Cicero, ‘’De natura deorum’ ‘[On the Nature of Gods], I, 35 (XIII). 6. ^Epictetus, ‘ ‘Discourses’ ‘, B, 19, 1 in ‘ ‘Discourses, Fragments, Handbook’ ‘, trans. Robin Hard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. {{ISBN|0199595186}}. 7. ^Origen, ‘ ‘ Contra Celsum’ ‘, trans. Henry Chadwick. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965. II, 20, 340.55-342.61. 8. ^Locke, John.’ ‘Essay Concerning Human Understanding’ ‘, XXI. 9. ^Spinoza, Baruch. ‘ ‘Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrata’ ’ [Ethics, Demonstrated in Geometrical Order], Pars II, Propositio XXXV, Scholium; Propositio XLVIII. 10. ^Baron d’Holbach, Paul-Henri Thiry. ‘ ‘The Illusion of Free Will’ ‘ in ‘ ‘System of Nature’ ‘. 11. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur. ‘ ‘Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung’ ‘[The World as Will and Idea]. I Band. Leipzig: Philipp Reclam jr., [s.a.], S.167. 12. ^Nietzsche, Friedrich. ‘ ‘Jenseits von Gut und Böse’ ‘[Beyond Good and Evil]. Leipzig: C.G.Neumann, 1886, S.21. 13. ^Wegner, Daniel. ‘ ‘The mind's best trick: how we experience conscious will’ ’ in ‘ ‘Trends in Cognitive Sciences’ ‘(2003), Vo;ume 7, no.2, p. 65-69. 14. ^Mele A.R. ‘’Free Will and Luck’ ‘. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 2006, p.189, {{ISBN|978-0-19-537439-1}}. 15. ^Honderich, Ted. Mind and Brain: A Theory of Determinism. Volume 1, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990, p.244. {{ISBN|978-0198242826}}. 16. ^Searle J. "Mental causation, conscious and unconscious", Int J.Philosophical Studies (2000), Volume 8, p.171-177. 17. ^Walter H. "Neurophilosophy of free will" in Oxford Handbook of Free Will, Oxford: Oxford University Press [2002], p.565-575. 18. ^1 2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,"Causal Determinism" 19. ^{{cite journal |last=Chown |first=Markus |date=June 1998 |title=Anything goes |journal=New Scientist |volume=158 |number=2157 |url=http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/toe_press.html}} 20. ^Pereboom, Derk, ' 'Meaning in life without free will ‘‘, in Oxford Handbook of Free Will, Oxford:Oxford University Press [2002], p.477-488. 21. ^Sam Harris, "Life Without Free Will" 22. ^Caruso Gregg D. ‘ ‘Free will skepticism and criminal behavior: A public health-quarantine model’ ‘.’ ‘Southwest Philosophy Review’ ‘(2016), Volume 32, no.1. 23. ^Baumeister R.F., Masicampo C.J., De Wall C.N.’ ‘Prosocial benefits of feeling free: disbelief in will increases aggression and reduces helpfulness’, ‘Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin’ (2009), Volume 35, no.2, p.260-268. 24. ^[https://www.uky.edu/~eushe2/Pajares/JamesDilemmaOfDeterminism.html, William James - The Dilemma of Determinism] 25. ^Naturalism.org, "Free Will and Naturalism: A Reply to Corliss Lamont" 26. ^Mazlovskis Arnis.’ ’On free will and determinism’ ‘.’ ‘Reliğiski-filozofiski raksti’ ‘[Religious-Philosophical Articles] (2015), XIX, p.22-42. ISSN 1407-1908. 27. ^The Project Gutenberg E Book: Benedict de Spinoza "The Ethics". Translated from the Latin by R.H.M.Elwes. Posting Date: May 28, 2009. Part V, Proposition VI. 2 : Determinism|Metaphysical theories |
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。