词条 | Non-aggression principle | ||||||||||||||||||||||||
释义 |
The non-aggression principle (NAP), also called the non-aggression axiom, the anti-coercion, zero aggression principle, or non-initiation of force, is an ethical stance asserting that aggression is inherently wrong. In this context, aggression is defined as initiating or threatening any forceful interference with an individual or their property.[1] In contrast to pacifism, it does not forbid forceful defense. The NAP is considered by some to be a defining principle of libertarianism, especially natural-rights libertarianism. It is also a prominent idea in anarcho-capitalism, classical liberalism and minarchism.[2][3][4][5] {{TOC limit|3}}HistoryThe non-aggression principle has existed in various forms. Although the principle has been traced back as far as antiquity, it was first formally described by this name by the Objectivist philosopher Ayn Rand and then further popularized by libertarian thinkers.[6][7] A number of authors have created their own formulation of the harm principle which NAP supporters argue as a form of non-aggression principle as shown in the table below.
JustificationsThe principle has been derived by various philosophical approaches, including:
Definitional issuesAbortionMany supporters and opponents of abortion rights justify their position on NAP grounds. One important question to determine whether or not abortion is consistent with NAP is at what stage of development a fertilized human egg cell can be considered a human being with the status and rights attributed to personhood. Some supporters of NAP argue this occurs at the moment of conception. Others argue that since they believe the fetus lacks sentience until a certain stage of development, it does not qualify as a human being, and as such may be considered property of the mother. Opponents of abortion, on the other hand, state sentience is not a qualifying factor. They refer to the animal rights discussion and point out the Argument from marginal cases that concludes NAP also applies to non-sentient (i.e. mentally handicapped) humans.[25] Another important question is whether an unwelcome fetus should be considered to be an unauthorized trespasser in its mother's body.[26] The non-aggression principle does not protect trespassers from the owners of the property on which they are trespassing.[27] It can also be argued that unwelcome fetuses are themselves committing aggression against their mothers, by taking materials (oxygen, water, nutrients) from her bloodstream, by injecting toxic metabolic end-products (carbon dioxide and creatinine) into her bloodstream, and by preparing to subject her to major medical/surgical trauma in the form of full-term labor and delivery. Objectivist philosopher Leonard Peikoff has argued that a fetus has no right to life inside the womb because it is not an "independently existing, biologically formed organism, let alone a person."[28] Pro-choice libertarian Murray Rothbard held the same stance, maintaining that abortion is justified at any time during pregnancy if the fetus is no longer welcome inside its mother.[29] Likewise, other pro-choice supporters base their argument on criminal trespass.[30] In that case, they claim, NAP is not violated when the fetus is forcibly removed, with deadly force if need be, from the mother’s body, just as NAP is not violated when an owner removes from the owner’s property an unwanted visitor who is not willing to leave voluntarily. Libertarian theorist Walter Block follows this line of argument but makes a distinction between evicting the fetus prematurely so that it dies and actively killing it (see Libertarian perspectives on abortion). Pro-life libertarians, however, argue that because the parents were actively involved in creating a new human life and that life has not consented to his or her own existence, that life is in the womb by necessity and no parasitism or trespassing is involved (see also legal necessity). They state that as the parents are responsible for that life's position, NAP would be violated when that life is killed with abortive techniques. Intellectual property rightsNAP is defined as applicable to any unauthorized actions towards a person’s physical property. Supporters of NAP disagree on whether it should apply to intellectual property (IP) rights as well as physical property rights.[31] Some argue that because intellectual concepts are non-rivalrous, intellectual property rights are unnecessary.[32] while others argue that intellectual property rights are as valid and important as physical ones.[33] InterventionsThough NAP is meant to guarantee an individual’s sovereignty, libertarians greatly differ on the conditions under which NAP applies. Especially unsolicited intervention by others, either to prevent society from being harmed by the individual’s actions or to prevent an incompetent individual from being harmed by his own (in)actions, is an important issue.[34] The debate centers on topics like the age of consent for children,[35][36][37] intervention counseling (i.e. for addicted persons, or in case of domestic violence),[38][39] involuntary commitment and involuntary treatment with regards to mental illness,[40] medical assistance (i.e. prolonged life support vs euthanasia in general and for the senile or comatose in particular),[41][42] human organ trade,[43][44][45] state paternalism (including economic intervention)[46][47][48] and foreign intervention by states.[49][50] Other discussion topics on whether intervention is in line with NAP include nuclear weapons proliferation,[51][52] and human trafficking and (illegal) immigration.[53][54][55] StatesSome libertarians justify the existence of a minimal state on the grounds that anarchism implies that the non-aggression principle is optional because the enforcement of laws is open to competition.[56] They claim competing law enforcement would always result in war and the rule of the most powerful. Anarcho-capitalists usually respond to this argument that this presumed outcome of coercive competition (e.g. PMCs or PDAs that enforce local law) is not likely because of the very high cost, in lives and economically, of war. They claim that war drains those involved and leaves non-combatant parties as the most powerful, economically and militarily, ready to take over.[57][58][59] Therefore, anarcho-capitalists claim that in practice, and in more advanced societies with large institutions that have a responsibility to protect their vested interests, disputes are most likely to be settled peacefully.[60][61] Anarcho-capitalists also point out that a state monopoly of law enforcement does not necessarily make NAP present throughout society as corruption and corporatism, as well as lobby group clientelism in democracies, favor only certain people or organizations. Anarcho-capitalists aligned with the Rothbardian philosophy generally contend that the state violates the non-aggression principle by its very nature because, it is argued, governments necessarily use force against those who have not stolen private property, vandalized private property, assaulted anyone, or committed fraud.[60][62][63]TaxationProponents of the NAP see taxes as a violation of NAP, while critics of the NAP argue that because of the free-rider problem in case security is a public good, enough funds would not be obtainable by voluntary means to protect individuals from aggression of a greater severity. The latter therefore accept taxation, and consequently a breach of NAP with regard to any free-riders, as long as no more is levied than is necessary to optimise protection of individuals against aggression.{{citation needed|date=November 2011}} Geolibertarians, who following the classical economists and Georgists adhere to the Lockean labor theory of property, argue that land value taxation is fully compatible with the NAP.{{citation needed|date=May 2014}} Anarcho-capitalists argue that the protection of individuals against aggression is self-sustaining like any other valuable service, and that it can be supplied without coercion by the free market much more effectively and efficiently than by a government monopoly.[64] Their approach, based on proportionality in justice and damage compensation, argues that full restitution is compatible with both retributivism and a utilitarian degree of deterrence while consistently maintaining NAP in a society.[58][65][66] They extend their argument to all public goods and services traditionally funded through taxation, like security offered by dikes.[67]Support and criticism{{multiple issues|{{original research section|date=May 2012}}{{refimprove section|date=May 2012}}{{POV section|date=April 2016}}{{rewrite section|date=April 2016}}}} Supporters of the NAP often appeal to it in order to argue for the immorality of theft, vandalism, assault, and fraud. Compared to nonviolence, the non-aggression principle does not preclude violence used in self-defense or defense of others.[68] Many supporters argue that NAP opposes such policies as victimless crime laws, taxation, and military drafts. NAP is the foundation of libertarian philosophy.[69] NAP faces two kinds of criticism: the first holds that the principle is immoral, and the second argues that it is impossible to apply consistently in practice; respectively, consequentialist or deontological criticisms, and inconsistency criticisms. Libertarian academic philosophers have noted the implausible results consistently applying the principle yields: for example, Professor Matt Zwolinski notes that, because pollution necessarily violates the NAP by encroaching (even if slightly) on other people's property, consistently applying the NAP would prohibit driving, starting a fire, and other activities necessary to the maintenance of industrial society.[70] Moral criticisms{{main article|Morality}}NAP does not allow for positive rightsCritics argue that the non-aggression principle is not ethical because it opposes the initiation of force even when they would consider the results of such initiation to be morally superior to the alternatives that they have identified. In arguing against the NAP, philosopher Matt Zwolinski has proposed the following scenario: "Suppose that by imposing a very, very small tax on billionaires, I could provide life-saving vaccination for tens of thousands of desperately poor children. Even if we grant that taxation is aggression, and that aggression is generally wrong, is it really so obvious that the relatively minor aggression involved in these examples is wrong, given the tremendous benefit it produces?"[70] Incompatibility with driving and other civilizational necessitiesZwolinski also notes that the NAP is incompatible with any practice that produces any pollution, because pollution encroaches on the property rights of others. Therefore, the NAP prohibits both driving and starting fires. Citing Professor David Friedman, Professor Zwolinski notes that the NAP is unable to place a sensible limitation on risk-creating behavior, arguing: {{quote|Of course, almost everything we do imposes some risk of harm on innocent persons. We run this risk when we drive on the highway (what if we suffer a heart attack, or become distracted), or when we fly airplanes over populated areas. Most of us think that some of these risks are justifiable, while others are not, and that the difference between them has something to do with the size and likelihood of the risked harm, the importance of the risky activity, and the availability and cost of less risky activities. But considerations like this carry zero weight in the NAP’s absolute prohibition on aggression. That principle seems compatible with only two possible rules: either all risks are permissible (because they are not really aggression until they actually result in a harm), or none are (because they are). And neither of these seems sensible.}} Innocent persons problemSome critics use the example of the trolley problem to invalidate NAP. In case of the runaway trolley, headed for five victims tied to the track, NAP does not allow a trolley passenger to flip the switch that diverts the trolley to a different track if there is a person tied to that track. That person would have been unharmed if nothing was done, therefore by flipping the switch NAP is violated. Another example often cited by critics is human shields. Some supporters argue that no one initiates force if their only option for self-defense is to use force against a greater number of people as long as they were not responsible for being in the position they are in. Murray Rothbard's and Walter Block's formulations of NAP avoid these objections by either specifying that the NAP applies only to a civilized context (and not 'lifeboat situations') or that it applies only to legal rights (as opposed to general morality). Thus a starving man may, in consonance with general morality, break into a hunting cabin and steal food, but nevertheless he is aggressing, i.e. violating the NAP, and (by most rectification theories) should pay compensation.[71] Critics argue that the legal rights approach might allow people who can afford to pay a sufficiently large amount of compensation to get away with murder. They point out that local law, though based on NAP, may vary from proportional compensation to capital punishment to no compensation at all.[58] Non-physical aggressionOther critics state that the NAP is unethical because it does not provide for the violent prohibition of, and thereby supposedly legitimizes, several forms of aggression that do not involve intrusion on property rights, such as verbal sexual harassment, defamation, boycotting, noninvasive striking, and noninvasive discrimination. If a victim thus provoked would turn to physical violence, according to the NAP, he would be labeled an aggressor. Supporters of the NAP, however, state that boycotting[72][73] and defamation[74][75] both constitute freedoms of speech and that boycotting,[72][73] noninvasive striking,[73][76] and noninvasive discrimination[77] all constitute freedoms of association, and that both freedoms of association and of speech are nonaggressive. Supporters also point out that prohibiting physical retaliation against an action is not itself condonement of said action,[78] and that generally there are other, nonphysical means by which one can combat social ills (e.g., discrimination) that do not violate the NAP.[73][77] Some supporters also state that while, most of the time, individuals choose voluntarily to engage in situations that may cause some degree of mental battering, this mental battering begins, when it cannot be avoided, to constitute unauthorized physical overload of the senses (i.e., eardrum and retina) and that the NAP, at that point, does apply. Many supporters consider verbal and written threats of imminent physical violence sufficient justification for a defensive response in a physical manner.[79][80] Such threats would then constitute a legitimate limit to permissible speech. Because freedom of association entails the right of owners to choose who is permitted to enter or remain on their premises, legitimate property owners may also impose limitation on speech. For example, the owner of a theatre, wishing to avoid a stampede, may prohibit those on her property from calling ‘fire!’ without just cause.[81] The owner of a bank, however, may not prohibit anyone from urging the general public to a bank run,[72] except insofar as this occurs on the property of said owner. H. L. Mencken, a writer who influenced many libertarians, puts an ethical limit on the freedom of speech: {{quote|I believe there is a limit beyond which free speech cannot go, but it's a limit that's very seldom mentioned. It's the point where free speech begins to collide with the right to privacy. I do not think there are any other conditions to free speech. I've got a right to say and believe anything I please, but I have not got a right to press it on anybody else. [...] Nobody's got a right to be a nuisance to his neighbors.| Mencken (1880–1956) in a 1948 interview with Donald H. Kirkley for the Library of Congress.[82]}} Supporters also consider physical threats of imminent physical violence (e.g., pointing a firearm at innocent people, stocking up nuclear weapons that cannot be used discriminately against specific individual aggressors) sufficient justification for a defensive response in a physical manner.[83][84][80] Such threats would then constitute a legitimate limit to permissible action. Inconsistency criticisms{{main article|Applied ethics}}Natural resources and environmental pollutionCritics argue it is not possible to uphold NAP when protecting the environment as most pollution can never be traced back to the party that caused it. They therefore claim that only general broad government regulations will be able to protect the environment. Supporters cite the problem of the tragedy of the commons and argue that free-market environmentalism will be much more effective in conserving nature.[85][86] Political theorist Hillel Steiner emphasizes that all things made come from natural resources and that the validity of any rights to those made things depends on the validity of the rights to the natural resources.[87] If land was stolen then anyone buying produce from that land would not be the legitimate owner of the goods. Also, if natural resources cannot be privately owned but are, and always will be, the property of all of mankind then NAP would be violated if such a resource would be used without everybody’s consent (see the Lockean proviso and free-market anarchism).[88] Libertarian philosopher Roderick Long points out that, as natural resources are required not only for the production of goods but for the production of the human body as well, the very concept of self-ownership can only exist if the land itself is privately owned.[89] Criticism of NAP as an absolute rather than relative conceptConsequentialist libertarian David Friedman, who believes that the NAP should be understood as a relative rather than absolute principle, defends his view by using a Sorites argument. Friedman begins by stating what he considers obvious: A neighbor aiming his flashlight at someone's property is not aggression, or if it is, it is only aggression in a trivial technical sense. However, aiming at the same property with a gigawatt laser is certainly aggression by any reasonable definition. Yet both flashlight and laser shine photons onto the property, so there must be some cutoff point of how many photons one is permitted to shine upon a property before it is considered aggression. But the cutoff point cannot be found by deduction alone, because of the Sorites paradox, so the non-aggression principle is necessarily ambiguous. Friedman points out the difficulty of undertaking any activity that poses a certain amount of risk to third parties (e.g. flying) if the permission of thousands of people that might be affected by the activity is required.[90]See also{{div col|colwidth=30em}}
References1. ^{{cite encyclopedia |last=Long|first=Roderick |authorlink=Roderick T. Long |editor-first=Ronald |editor-last=Hamowy |editor-link=Ronald Hamowy |encyclopedia=The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism |url= https://books.google.com/books?id=yxNgXs3TkJYC |year=2008 |publisher= SAGE; Cato Institute |location= Thousand Oaks, CA |isbn= 978-1-4129-6580-4 |oclc=750831024| lccn = 2008009151 |pages=357–60 |doi= 10.4135/9781412965811.n219|quote=...except in response to the initiation ... of similar forcible interference .... |ref= |chapter=|title=Nonaggression Axiom }} 2. ^{{Cite web | url=http://fff.org/explore-freedom/article/the-morality-of-libertarianism/ | title=The Morality of Libertarianism | publisher=The Future of Freedom Foundation| accessdate=2016-03-16}} 3. ^{{Cite web | url=http://archive.lewrockwell.com/block/block26.html | title=The Non-Aggression Axiom of Libertarianism|publisher=Lew Rockwell | accessdate=2016-03-22}} 4. ^{{Cite web | url=https://www.theadvocates.org/aggression/| title=What is the "non-aggression principle"? | publisher=Advocates for Small Government | accessdate=2016-03-22}} 5. ^{{Cite web|url=http://www.yaliberty.org/posts/discovering-libertarianism-non-aggression-principle-introduction| title=Discovering Libertarianism – Non-Aggression Principle | publisher=Young Americans for Liberty | accessdate=2016-03-22}} 6. ^{{cite web |url=http://libertyunbound.com/sites/files/printarchive/Liberty_Magazine_January_2005.pdf |title= Freedom: What’s Right vs What Works (Liberty Magazine, January 2005, Vol 15 No 1, pp. 31–39) |author1=Charles Murray |author2=David Friedman |author3=David Boaz |author4=R.W. Bradford |last-author-amp=yes |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 7. ^{{cite web |url=http://archive.lewrockwell.com/orig/block1.html |title= Jonah Goldberg and the Libertarian Axiom on Non-Aggression (LewRockwell.com, June 28, 2001) |author= Walter Block |accessdate=2011-11-17 }} 8. ^{{cite web |url=https://wiki.mises.org/wiki/Principle_of_non-aggression#Historical_formulations_and_background |title=Principle of Non-Aggression |publisher=The Mises Institute | accessdate=2016-01-15}} 9. ^{{cite web |url=https://wiki.mises.org/wiki/Principle_of_non-aggression#Historical_formulations_and_background |title=Principle of Non-Aggression |author=Thomas Jefferson | accessdate=2016-01-15}} 10. ^{{cite web |url=http://tjrs.monticello.org/letter/1380 |title=Extract from Thomas Jefferson to Francis Walker Gilmer, 7 June 1816 | author=Thomas Jefferson |publisher=Thomas Jefferson Foundation |work=Jefferson Quotes & Family Letters |accessdate=7 April 2017}} 11. ^{{cite web |url=https://wiki.mises.org/wiki/Principle_of_non-aggression#Historical_formulations_and_background |title=Principle of Non-Aggression |author=Herbert Spencer | accessdate=2016-01-15}} 12. ^{{cite web |url=https://wiki.mises.org/wiki/Principle_of_non-aggression#Historical_formulations_and_background |title=Principle of Non-Aggression |author=John Stuart Mill | accessdate=2016-01-15}} 13. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.barefootsworld.net/nockoets2.html |title=Our Enemy, the State |author=Albert J. Nock | accessdate=2016-01-15}} 14. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.ccsindia.org/ccsindia/lssreader/2lssreader.pdf |title=The Nature of Government (December 1963, from The Virtue of Selfishness, 1961, 1964) |author=Ayn Rand |accessdate=2011-11-15 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20111014103029/http://www.ccsindia.org/ccsindia/lssreader/2lssreader.pdf |archivedate=2011-10-14 |df= }} 15. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.freedomkeys.com/ar-rootsofwar.htm |title=The Roots of War (June 1966, excerpts) |author=Ayn Rand |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 16. ^{{cite web |url=http://freedomkeys.com/faithandforce.htm |title=Faith and Force: The Destroyers of the Modern World (1960, 1967, excerpts) |author=Ayn Rand |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 17. ^{{cite web |url=http://archive.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard26.html |title=War, Peace, and the State (April 1963) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 18. ^{{cite web |url=http://archive.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard47.html |title=Hoppephobia (2004 LewRockwell.com reprint from Liberty, Vol. 3 No. 4, March 1990, pp. 11–12.) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2012-01-05 }} 19. ^{{Cite journal|title=Review Article: The New Liberalism|journal=British Journal of Political Science| volume= 13|issue= 1|date= January 1993|pages= 93–123) |author=Norman P. Barry |jstor = 193781|doi=10.1017/s000712340000315x}} 20. ^For example: {{cite book |last=Koehn |first=Daryl |year=2005 |title=The nature of evil |location=New York |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |pages=3–8 |isbn=1403968942 |oclc=56064628 |doi=10.1057/9781403979377 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oUfHAAAAQBAJ}} And: {{cite book |editor-last=Schweiker |editor-first=William |editor-link=William Schweiker |year=2005 |title=The Blackwell companion to religious ethics |location=Malden, MA |publisher=Blackwell Publishing |isbn=0631216340 |oclc=55008191 |doi=10.1002/9780470997031 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XK2kQJqyXdEC}} 21. ^For example: {{cite book |editor1-last=Waal |editor1-first=Frans B. M. de |editor1-link=Frans de Waal |editor2-last=Churchland |editor2-first=Patricia Smith |editor2-link=Patricia Churchland |editor3-last=Pievani |editor3-first=Telmo |editor4-last=Parmigiani |editor4-first=Stefano |year=2014 |title=Evolved morality: the biology and philosophy of human conscience |location=Leiden; Boston |publisher=Brill Publishers |isbn=9789004263871 |oclc=866620305 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kkkJAwAAQBAJ}} And: {{cite book |editor-last=Fassin |editor-first=Didier |editor-link=Didier Fassin |year=2012 |title=A companion to moral anthropology |series=Blackwell companions to anthropology |volume=20 |location=Hoboken, NJ |publisher=Wiley-Blackwell |isbn=9780470656457 |oclc=773020929 |doi=10.1002/9781118290620 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UGFJrO1I274C}} 22. ^{{cite web |url= http://www.theobjectivestandard.com/issues/2013-winter/libertarianism-vs-radical-capitalism.asp |title= Libertarianism vs. Radical Capitalism (The Objective Standard, Vol. 8 No. 4, Winter 2013-2014) | author=Craig Biddle |accessdate=2013-11-11 }} 23. ^{{cite web |url= http://www.aynrand.org/site/PageServer?pagename=ari_ayn_rand_the_objectivist_ethics |title= The Objectivist Ethics (The Virtue of Selfishness, 1961) | author=Ayn Rand |accessdate=2012-11-05 }} 24. ^Kinsella, Stephan. "Punishment and Proportionality: the Estoppel Approach." Journal of Libertarian Studies 12, No. 1 (1996): 51–73. 25. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.libertarianfaq.org/index.php?title=Are_libertarians_pro_choice_or_pro_life%3F |title=Are libertarians pro choice or pro life? (Libertarian FAQ Wikipage, January 2, 2010) |author=Various authors |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 26. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.str.org/articles/trespassing-in-the-womb#.VXIUO0aRzak|title=Trespassing in the Womb - Stand to Reason|author=|date=|website=www.str.org|accessdate=28 March 2018}} 27. ^{{cite web|url=http://c4ss.org/content/13144|title=Is Property Theft?|author=|date=|website=c4ss.org|accessdate=28 March 2018}} 28. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.peikoff.com/essays_and_articles/abortion-rights-are-pro-life/ |title=Abortion Rights are Pro-Life |author=Leonard Peikoff |accessdate=2011-11-16 }} 29. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/rothbard/newlibertywhole.asp#p94 |title=For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto (1973, 1978, 2002 online ed, Chapter 6) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2011-11-16 }} 30. ^{{cite web |url=http://libertarianpapers.org/articles/2010/lp-2-32.pdf |title=Rejoinder to Wisniewski on Abortion (Libertarian Papers Vol. 2, Art. No. 32, 2010) |author=Walter Block |accessdate=2011-12-21 }} 31. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/libhe/libhe014.htm |title=Intellectual Property: The Late Nineteenth Century Libertarian Debate (Libertarian Alliance, 1995, ISBN 1-85637-281-2) |author=Wendy McElroy |accessdate=2011-11-17 }} 32. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/journals/jls/15_2/15_2_1.pdf |title=Against Intellectual Property (Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. 15, No. 2, Spring 2001, pp. 1–53) |author=N. Stephan Kinsella |accessdate=2011-11-17 }} 33. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.lysanderspooner.org/intellect/contents.htm |title=The Law of Intellectual Property: An Essay on the Right of Authors and Inventors to a Perpetual Property in Their Ideas (Bella Marsh, Boston, 1855) |author=Lysander Spooner |accessdate=2011-11-17 }} 34. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.thefreemanonline.org/featured/reflections-on-self-responsibility-and-libertarianism/ |title=Reflections on Self-Responsibility and Libertarianism (The Freeman April 2001, Vol. 51, No. 4) |author=Nathaniel Branden |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 35. ^{{cite web |url=http://crazyforliberty.com/2008/05/07/anarchism-age-of-consent-laws-and-the-dallas-accord-wayne-allyn-root.aspx |title=Anarchism, Age of Consent Laws and the Dallas Accord (Crazy for Liberty, May 7, 2008) |author=Wayne Allyn Root |accessdate=2011-11-22 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20111204103329/http://crazyforliberty.com/2008/05/07/anarchism-age-of-consent-laws-and-the-dallas-accord-wayne-allyn-root.aspx |archivedate=December 4, 2011 |df= }} 36. ^{{cite web |url=http://lonelylibertarian.blogspot.com/2008/04/age-of-consent.html |title=Age of Consent (The Lonely Libertarian, April 25, 2008) |author=Lonely Libertarian |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 37. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.thedegree.org/polin010.pdf |title=Sex, Coercion, and the Age of Consent (Libertarian Alliance, 1981, ISBN 1-85637-190-5) |author=Max O’Connor |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 38. ^{{cite web |url=http://jme.bmj.com/content/30/5/453.full.pdf |title=Pressure and coercion in the care for the addicted: ethical perspectives (Journal of Medical Ethics, 2004, No. 30, pp. 453–58) |author= M J P A Janssens|accessdate=2011-11-22 |display-authors=etal}} 39. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/enlightened-living/201006/addiction-self-responsibility-and-the-importance-choice |title= Addiction, Self-responsibility and the Importance of Choice: Why AA doesn’t work (Psychology Today, June 3, 2010) |author=Michael J. Formica |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 40. ^{{cite web|url=http://www.cato-unbound.org/archives/august-2012/|title=Mental Health and the Law|author=|date=1 August 2012|website=cato-unbound.org|accessdate=28 March 2018}} 41. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/journals/jls/4_3/4_3_2.pdf |title=Libertarianism and Legal Paternalism (The Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. IV, No. 3, Summer 1980, pp. 255–65) |author=John Hospers |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 42. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.humblelibertarian.com/2011/11/euthanasia-first-in-netherlands.html |title=A Euthanasia First in the Netherlands (The Humble Libertarian, November 9, 2011) |author=W E Messamore (ed.) |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 43. ^{{cite web |url=https://independent.academia.edu/DannyFrederick/Papers/159192/A_Competitive_Market_in_Human_Organs |title=A Competitive Market in Human Organs (Libertarian Papers, Vol. 2, No. 27, 2010, pp. 1–21, online at libertarianpapers.org ) |author=Danny Frederick |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 44. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.graemeklass.com/economics/organ-trading/ |title=Organ Trading (The Libertarian Engineer, April 6, 2011) |author=Graeme Klass |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 45. ^{{cite web |url=http://notes.kateva.org/2011/09/humanity-experiment-has-mixed-results.html |title=The humanity experiment has mixed results: Organ trade and enslaving the disabled (Gordon’s Notes, September 9, 2011) |author=John Gordon |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 46. ^{{cite web |url=http://uchicagolaw.typepad.com/faculty/2007/01/libertarian_pat.html |title=Libertarian Paternalism (University of Chicago Law School, January 20, 2007) |author=Cass Sunstein |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 47. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/daily/2965 |title=Libertarian Paternalism (Mises Daily, May 21, 2008) |author=David Gordon |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 48. ^{{cite web |url=http://volokh.com/2010/04/19/richard-thaler-responds/ |title=Richard Thaler Responds to Critics of Libertarian Paternalism (The Volokh Conspiracy April 15, 2010) |author=Ilya Somin |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 49. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/forep/forep008.pdf |title=A Few Words On Non-Intervention (Libertarian Alliance reprint of J.S. Mill’s essay from Fraser’s Magazine, 1859) |author=John Stuart Mill |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 50. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.nolanchart.com/article8684-nonintervention.html |title=Non-Intervention (The continuing rEVOlution, May 20, 2011) |author=George Dance |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 51. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.walterblock.com/wp-content/uploads/publications/theory_gun_control.pdf |title=Toward a Universal Libertarian Theory of Gun (Weapon) Control: A Spatial and Geographycal Analysis (Ethics, Place and Environment, Vol. 3, No. 3, May 2000, pp. 289–98) |author1=Walter Block |author2=Matthew Block |lastauthoramp=yes |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 52. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.bestsyndication.com/2005/A-H/DAVIS-Mike/112505_nuclear_weapons.htm |title=Who should Own Nuclear Weapons (Best Syndication, November 25, 2005) |author=Michael Gilson-De Lemos |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 53. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/daily/1980 |title=The Libertarian Immigration Conundrum (Mises Daily, December 8, 2005) |author=Per Bylund |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 54. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.isil.org/resources/libertydocs/immigration.html |title=Immigration: Controversies, Libertarian Principles and Modern Abolition (International Society for Individual Liberty, 2001) |author=Ken Schoolland |accessdate=2011-11-22 }} 55. ^{{cite web |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=12YDLZq8rT4 |title=Globalisation is Good (Channel 4 UK documentary, 2003, on Youtube.com) |author=Johan Norberg |accessdate=2012-11-18 }} 56. ^{{cite web |url=http://web.calstatela.edu/faculty/areed2/LongXXXMachan.pdf |title=Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country? (Ashgate Publishing, 2008) |author=Roderick T. Long & Tibor R. Machan (ed.) |accessdate=2011-11-24 |deadurl=bot: unknown |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20160306172845/http://web.calstatela.edu/faculty/areed2/LongXXXMachan.pdf |archivedate=2016-03-06 |df= }} 57. ^{{cite web |url=http://libertarian.co.uk/lapubs/legan/legan016.pdf |title=Privately Produced Law (Libertarian Alliance reprint, 1991, ISBN 1-85637-053-4) |author=Tom W. Bell |accessdate=2011-11-24 }} 58. ^1 2 {{cite web |url=http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Libertarian/Machinery_of_Freedom/MofF_Chapter_29.html |title=Police, Courts and Law – On the Market (The Machinery of Freedom, 1989, Chapter 29) |author=David D. Friedman |accessdate=2011-11-12 }} 59. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.daviddfriedman.com/laws_order/index.shtml |title=Law’s Order: What Economics Has To Do With Law And Why It Matters (Princeton University Press, 2000) |author=David D. Friedman |accessdate=2011-11-24 }} 60. ^1 {{cite web |url=http://archive.lewrockwell.com/orig6/molyneux1.html |title=The Stateless Society (LewRockwell.com, October 24, 2005) |last=Molyneux |first= Stefan |authorlink=Stefan Molyneux |accessdate=2011-11-17}} 61. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/journals/jls/14_1/14_1_2.pdf |title=The Private Production of Defense (Journal of Libertarian Studies, 14:1, Winter 1998–1999, pp. 27–52) |author=Hans-Hermann Hoppe |accessdate=2011-11-24 }} 62. ^{{cite web |url=http://praxeology.net/Anarconst2.pdf|title=Market Anarchism as Constitutionalism (Anarchism/Minarchism, 2008, Chapter 9) |author=Roderick T. Long |accessdate=2011-11-16 }} 63. ^{{cite web |url=http://gaplauche.com/docs/persistentanarchyapsa2006.pdf |title=On the Social Contract and the Persistence of Anarchy (American Political Science Association, 2006) |author=Geoffrey Allen Plauché (Louisiana State University, Baton Rouge, LA) |accessdate=2011-11-16 }} 64. ^"Review of Kosanke's Instead of Politics – Don Stacy" Libertarian Papers Vol. 3, Art. No. 3 (2011) 65. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.la-articles.org.uk/libertarian_restitution.htm |title=Why Libertarian Restitution Beats State-Retribution and State-Leniency (2005) |author=J. C. Lester |accessdate=2011-11-12 }} 66. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/daily/2496 |title=Punishment and Proportionality (The Ethics of Liberty, 1982, Chapter 13) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2011-11-12 }} 67. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/daily/2537 |title=Can Dikes Be Private? : An Argument Against Public Goods Theory (Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. 20, No. 4, Fall 2006, pp. 21–40) |author=Philipp Bagus |accessdate=2011-11-17 }} 68. ^{{cite web |url= http://archive.lewrockwell.com/block/block26.html |title= The Non-Aggression Axiom of Libertarianism (LewRockwell.com, February 17, 2003) | author=Walter Block |accessdate=2011-11-12 }} 69. ^1 {{cite web |url=http://blog.mises.org/18608/the-relation-between-the-non-aggression-principle-and-property-rights-a-response-to-division-by-zer0/ |title=The relation between the non-aggression principle and property rights (Mises Economics Blog, October 4, 2011) |author=Stephan Kinsella |accessdate=2011-11-25 }} 70. ^1 {{cite web |url=http://www.libertarianism.org/blog/six-reasons-libertarians-should-reject-non-aggression-principle|title=Six Reasons Libertarians Should Reject the Non-Aggression Principle |author=Matt Zwolinski |accessdate=2014-12-01}} 71. ^{{cite web |url=https://mises.org/daily/1628 |title=Lifeboat Situations (The Ethics of Liberty, 1982, Chapter 20) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2011-11-15 }} 72. ^1 2 Murray N. Rothbard, "Freedom of Speech," §1 of "Personal Liberty," ch. 6, in "Libertarian Applications to Current Problems," pt. 2 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), pp. 117–18. 73. ^1 2 3 Murray N. Rothbard, "The Boycott," ch. 18, in "A Theory of Liberty," pt. 2 of The Ethics of Liberty (New York, N. Y.: New York University Press, 1998; orig. 1982), pp. 131–32. Cf., pp. 77, 79, 240. 74. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Freedom of Speech," §1 of "Personal Liberty," ch. 6, in "Libertarian Applications to Current Problems," pt. 2 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), pp. 116–17. 75. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Knowledge, True and False," ch. 16, in "A Theory of Liberty," pt. 2 of The Ethics of Liberty (New York, N. Y.: New York University Press, 1998; orig. 1982), pp. 121–22, 126–28. 76. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Anti-Strike Laws," §4 of "Involuntary Servitude," ch. 5, in "Libertarian Applications to Current Problems," pt. 2 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), pp. 102–04. Cf., pp. 93, 118. Cf., The Ethics of Liberty, pp. 77, 132. 77. ^1 Murray N. Rothbard, "Street Rules," §2 of "The Public Sector, II: Streets and Roads," ch. 11, in "Libertarian Applications to Current Problems," pt. 2 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), pp. 255–56. Cf., pp. 103, 128. 78. ^Professor Murray N. Rothbard, in "Natural Law and Natural Rights," ch. 4, in "Introduction: Natural Law," pt. 1 of The Ethics of Liberty (New York, N. Y.: New York University Press, 1998; orig. 1982), p. 24, writes:{{quote|"Right" has cogently and trenchantly been defined by Professor Sadowsky:{{quote|When we say that one has the right to do certain things we mean this and only this, that it would be immoral for another, alone or in combination, to stop him from doing this by the use of physical force or the threat thereof. We do not mean that any use a man makes of his property within the limits set forth is necessarily a moral use?}} Sadowsky's definition highlights the crucial distinction we shall make throughout this work between a man's right and the morality or immorality of his exercise of that right. We will contend that it is a man's right to do whatever he wishes with his person; it is his right not to be molested or interfered with by violence from exercising that right. But what may be the moral or immoral ways of exercising that right is a question of personal ethics rather than of political philosophy—which is concerned solely with matters of right, and of the proper or improper exercise of physical violence in human relations. The importance of this crucial distinction cannot be overemphasized. Or, as Elisha Hurlbut concisely put it: "The exercise of a faculty by an individual] is its only use. The manner of its exercise is one thing; that involves a question of morals. The right to its exercise is another thing."}}Cf., pp. 25, 77, 79, 98 (note 2), 100–01, 107, 121, 124 (note 2), 127, 131–33, 136, 138, 142, 146, 151–53, 173–74, 220, 222. 79. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Self-Defense," ch. 12, in "A Theory of Liberty," pt. 2 of The Ethics of Liberty (New York, N. Y.: New York University Press, 1998; orig. 1982), pp. 77–78, 80. Cf., For a New Liberty, p. 27. 80. ^1 Linda & Morris Tannehill, The Market for Liberty (San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, October 1993; orig. March 1970), pp. 4, 10. Cf., pp. 77, 80 81. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Property Rights and 'Human Rights'," §5 of "Property and Exchange," ch. 2, in "The Libertarian Creed," pt. 1 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), pp. 52–53. Cf., pp. 85–86, 115. 82. ^{{cite web |url=http://blog.infinitemonkeysblog.com/?q=node/7319 |title=Fred Phelps, Freedom of Speech and 'the Last Limits of the Endurable' (Ben’s Blog on Infinite Monkeys, Fri, 10/08/2010) |author=Ben’s Blog |accessdate=2011-11-26 }} 83. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "Self-Defense," ch. 12, in "A Theory of Liberty," pt. 2 of The Ethics of Liberty (New York, N. Y.: New York University Press, 1998; orig. 1982), pp. 77–78, 80. Cf., pp. 81–82, 189–91, 194. 84. ^Murray N. Rothbard, "The Nonaggression Axiom," §1 of "Property and Exchange," ch. 2, in "The Libertarian Creed," pt. 1 of The Libertarian Manifesto (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2006; orig. 1973, 1978), p. 27. Cf., p. 335. 85. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.cato.org/pubs/journal/cj2n1/cj2n1-2.pdf |title=Law, Property Rights, and Air Pollution (Cato Journal, Vol. 2, No. 1, Spring 1982, pp. 55–99) |author=Murray N. Rothbard |accessdate=2011-11-24 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20110911075448/http://www.cato.org/pubs/journal/cj2n1/cj2n1-2.pdf |archivedate=2011-09-11 |df= }} 86. ^{{cite web |url=http://libertarianpapers.org/articles/2011/lp-3-10.pdf |title=Free Markets, Property Rights and Climate Change: How To Privatize Climate Policy (Libertarian Papers, Vol. 3, No. 10, 2011, pp. 1–29) |author=Graham Dawson |accessdate=2011-12-04 }} 87. ^{{cite web |url=http://bleedingheartlibertarians.com/2012/04/left-libertarianism-and-the-ownership-of-natural-resources/ |title=Left-Libertarianism and the Ownership of Natural Resources (Bleeding Heart Libertarians, April 24, 2012) |author=Hillel Steiner |accessdate=2012-07-07 }} 88. ^{{cite web |url=http://bleedingheartlibertarians.com/2012/04/natural-rights-and-natural-stuff/ |title=Natural Rights and Natural Stuff (Bleeding Heart Libertarians, April 23, 2012) |author=Eric Mack |accessdate=2012-07-07 }} 89. ^{{cite web |url=http://bleedingheartlibertarians.com/2012/04/self-ownership-and-external-property/ |title=Self-Ownership and External Property (Bleeding Heart Libertarians, April 25, 2012) |author=Roderick Long |accessdate=2012-07-07 }} 90. ^{{cite web |url=http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Libertarian/Machinery_of_Freedom/MofF_Chapter_41.html |title=Problems (The Machinery of Freedom, 1989, Chapter 41) |author=David D. Friedman |accessdate=2013-01-03 }} External links
4 : Anarcho-capitalism|Ethical principles|Social concepts|Libertarian terms |
||||||||||||||||||||||||
随便看 |
|
开放百科全书收录14589846条英语、德语、日语等多语种百科知识,基本涵盖了大多数领域的百科知识,是一部内容自由、开放的电子版国际百科全书。